[Search for users]
[Overall Top Noters]
[List of all Conferences]
[Download this site]
Title: | Topics of Interest to Women |
Notice: | V3 is closed. TURRIS::WOMANNOTES-V5 is open. |
Moderator: | REGENT::BROOMHEAD |
|
Created: | Thu Jan 30 1986 |
Last Modified: | Fri Jun 30 1995 |
Last Successful Update: | Fri Jun 06 1997 |
Number of topics: | 1078 |
Total number of notes: | 52352 |
680.0. "In Search of the 'Just War'" by VMSSPT::NICHOLS (It ain't easy being green) Tue Jan 29 1991 13:25
In Search of the Just War
John H Yoder
from the Boston Globe Focus Section Sunday 27-Jan-1991
without permission
(John H. Yoder is a former president of the Society of Christian Ethics,
professor of theology in the University of Notre Dame and Fellow of the
Institute for International Peace Studies.)
Since the fourth century, the majority view of Christian theologians
has been that although war is an evil, it may be justified when it can be
shown to be less evil than what some enemy threatens to do. A "just war"
has become the code designation for that stance, and the conflict in the
Persian Gulf has reignited the debate over whether there is such a thing as
a just wear or whether war can, in fact, be evaluated morally.
Ambrose and Augustine began reasoning in the just-war mode, though
quite unsystematically. Early medieval canon law codified it by determine
under what conditions participation in war needed absolution. Thomas
Aquinas (d. 1274) gave it a dozen pages in his "Summa Theologica."
Francisco de Vitoria (d. 1546) first wrote about it at book length, in the
interest of protecting the peoples of South America against the
depredations of the Iberian (Spain and Portugal) empires. Hugo Grotius
moved it into the language of internationl(sic) law. And a system of
treaties (Paris 1856, Geneva 1864, going on until the United Nations
conventions since 1948) spelled it out in procedural rules about blockades,
prisoners and the wounded, prohibited weapons, etc.
The "just war tradition," as its roots attest, is not one single
argument, but rather a multidimensional mode of evaluation that uses a
checklist of criteria to determine when the "lesser evil" claim can be
sustained and a particular war can be justified.
The value of this approach, in the mind of the moral theologian, is to
provide political and military officials with a framework for making
decisions about war. This is particularly useful if it helps call for
restraint, in the face of the many pressures that militate against
sobriety; or helps caution against "realism" or "cynicism" that denies the
possibility of moral reasoning in matters of war; or against the "crusading"
mood that claims a transcendent mandate or the "Rambo" mood, devoted to
proving the combatant's virility. Wherever in the public debate such
restraint is effective, the just war tradition is working.
The superficial impression, according to which the "just war" and
pacifism are the major opposing positions, is wrong. These two views agree
in their rejection of the crusade, of "realism" and of "Rambo," which are
the really threatening alternatives. They differ on specific cases, but
they agree with the initial presumption against war. War has the burden of
proof.
D o e s s y s t e m f o s t e r r e s t r a i n t?
Critics of the tradition sometimes ask: "Was there ever a just war?"
The question is helpful, as a way to learn from history, but as a way to
evaluate contested moral postures, it is not quite fair; no moral system is
validated by someone's living it out perfectly. The more helpful question
to ask is: "Does the system foster restraint? Can it say 'no' to a
particular war?"
What does it take to prove that the initial presumption against war is
overridden in a particular case? One set of criteria must apply before the
fact; jurists call them 'jus as bellum' - the right to go to war:
o The cause must be just
o The authority waging war must be a legitimate government.
o The ultimate objective ("intention") must be a secure, just future
peace.
o The motivation (also called "intention") must not be hatred or
desire for glory but selfless commitment to justice.
Another set of criteria ('jus in bello' - "fighting rightly") must govern
the prosecution of a war once undertaken:
o The means used must be necessary; no wanton destruction.
o Noncombatants must not be attacked directly and intentionally.
o Damage done must not be disproportionate.
o The means must be discriminating in order to meet the three above
criteria.
o The provisions on international law, customs, and treaties (e.g. the
Hague and Geneva conventions) must be respected.
A third set of criteria is more procedural, overlapping the two above
categories:
o Resort to war must be a last resort.
o Success must be probable
o The enemy must always be able to sue for peace.
The list could be extended, but this suffices to characterize the logic of
the system. All of these criteria are commonsensical, reasonable. Their
vocabulary is familiar. They depend on no religious warrant. Each of them
demands further definition, without which it is not in fact usable as
criterion, i.e., to measure with. That further definition (What cause is
"just"? What authority is "legitimate"?) will be supplied from the rest of
the value system of the respective person or group.
T r a d i t i o n ' s r e c e n t a p p l i c a t i o n
The tradition has been applied effectively twice in our recent history;
during the Vietnam War, when it provided the criteria whereby US citizens,
including a few thousand "selective conscientious objectors," without being
pacifist, rejected that war; and in 1980-1983, when Roman Catholic bishops
of the United States formally rejected nuclear war.
The Persian Gulf crisis is now showing us how familiar categories can
be appealed to on both sides of the domestic debate. In the last three
months, the leadership of most of the "mainstream" churches, including the
Roman Catholic bishops, has indicated that the war being projected in the
Persian Gulf would not meet the "just war" requirements. Others who claim
no less religious authority, claiming to apply the same tradition, take
the other side. Any reader can run down the above list of criteria and
fill in the blanks on either side.
Is the criterion of "legitimate authority" met internationally when the
United States outruns the original United Nations authorization? Can we
with integrity claim a UN mandate when we don't pay our own dues and when
we deny the right of the world community to judge our mining the harbors of
Nicaragua? When we refuse to negotiate in good faith on the laws of the
sea or on a test ban?
Is the criterion of "legitimate authority" met domestically when
despite powerful pressures, 46 senators vote against authorizing war? Was
the criterion of "last resort" met by making Jan. 15 an absolute deadline
and by President Bush's intransigence about not negotiating? Is the
criterion of serving a "future just and secure peace" met by destroying
the Iraqi infrastructure and by further arming both Israel and Syria? Is
the criterion of "proportionality" met when we measure all the likely
categories? Can the criterion of "civilian immunity" be met with the scale
of air war now being carried on?
These questions demonstrate four things:
o That since the just-war system is subject to such diverse
interpretations, as a whole it is not capable of yielding a clear, univocal
reading about a particular case.
o That the tradition does provide a set of concepts whereby public
debate about any particular war can proceed. It enables people with
conflicting values to talk past each other while using the same words,
contesting the meaning of the same facts.
o That when religious authorities base their pastoral guidance upon
commonsensical resources of this kind, their "faithful" are not very
faithful. The authority of ecclesiastical leaders is at risk when the
moral judgment they try to provide is based upon debatable readings as to
the facts.
o One of the tests of the tradition'/s working is its capacity to move
individuals to disobey unjust orders or laws. After "selective objection"
had been happening for several years in the Vietnam years, America's
traditional church hierarchies, Roman Catholic and Lutheran, recognized
that it was a bona fide implementation of the just-war tradition. Thus
far, no such advice has been given by bishops or synods to men and women
being sent to Saudi Arabia. Scant pastoral assistance has been available
to servicemen and women seeking help to determine whether they should
accept being sent to battle in the desert.
When once asked: "What do you think of Western civilization?" Gandhi
said, "I think it would be a good thing." The analogy is authentic. The
just-war tradition would be worthy of respect, in the eyes of the pacifist
on one side who wants more restraint, as in the eyes of the "realist" on
the other who wants less, if it were to keep its promise produce effective
discernment.
It would need to be implemented with some degree of clarity, to draw a
more-than-subjective line between the licit use of military force and the
forbidden. It would need to move citizens to opposition and persons in the
military to refusal to serve.
Failing to do that, it has the ambivalent value of a common language
system within which to formulate our disagreements.
T.R | Title | User | Personal Name | Date | Lines
|
---|