[Search for users] [Overall Top Noters] [List of all Conferences] [Download this site]

Conference rusure::math

Title:Mathematics at DEC
Moderator:RUSURE::EDP
Created:Mon Feb 03 1986
Last Modified:Fri Jun 06 1997
Last Successful Update:Fri Jun 06 1997
Number of topics:2083
Total number of notes:14613

1817.0. "FAQ frequently asked questions from sci.math" by STAR::ABBASI (only 21 days to go and counting...) Sat Nov 20 1993 01:03

    this note for FAQ (frequently asked questions) from sci.math

    it has lots of useful stuff.

    this is for those who might not have access to the net or
    might have missed this.

    \nasser
T.RTitleUserPersonal
Name
DateLines
1817.1FAQ 1 of 3STAR::ABBASIonly 21 days to go and counting...Sat Nov 20 1993 01:05625
Subject: sci.math: Frequently Asked Questions [1/3]
Originator: [email protected]
Organization: University of Waterloo
Date: Fri, 19 Nov 1993 14:03:31 GMT
 
Archive-Name: sci-math-faq/part1
Last-modified: October 26, 1993
Version: 5.0
 
This is the list of Frequently Asked Questions for sci.math (version 5.0).
Any contributions/suggestions/corrections are most welcome. Please use
* e-mail * on any comment concerning the FAQ list.
 
 
Section 1 of 3, questions 1Q to 5Q.
 
 
             Table of Contents
             -----------------
 
 1Q.- Fermat's Last Theorem, status of ..
 2Q.- Values of Record Numbers
 3Q.- Formula for prime numbers...
 4Q.- Digits of Pi, computation and references
 5Q.- Odd Perfect Number
 6Q.- Computer Algebra Systems, application of ..
 7Q.- Computer Algebra Systems, references to ..
 8Q.- Fields Medal, general info ..
 9Q.- Four Colour Theorem, proof of ..
10Q.- 0^0=1. A comprehensive approach
11Q.- 0.999... = 1. Properties of the real numbers ..
12Q.- There are three doors, The Monty Hall problem, Master Mind and
      other games ..
13Q.- Surface and Volume of the n-ball
14Q.- f(x)^f(x)=x, name of the function ..
15Q.- Projective plane of order 10 ..
16Q.- How to compute day of week of a given date
17Q.- Axiom of Choice and/or Continuum Hypothesis?
18Q.- Cutting a sphere into pieces of larger volume
19Q.- Pointers to Quaternions
20Q.- Erdos Number
21Q.- Why is there no Nobel in mathematics?
22Q.- General References and textbooks...
23Q.- Interest Rate...
24Q.- Euler's formula e^(i Pi) = - 1 ...
 
 
1Q:  What is the current status of Fermat's last theorem?
 
 
and
 
    Did Fermat prove this theorem? 
      
   
    Fermat's Last Theorem:
 
    There are no positive integers x,y,z, and n > 2 such that x^n + y^n = z^n.
 
    I heard that <insert name here> claimed to have proved it but later
    on the proof was found to be wrong. ...
 
A:  The status of FLT has remained remarkably constant.  Every few
    years, someone claims to have a proof ... but oh, wait, not quite.
 
    UPDATE... UPDATE... UPDATE
 
    Andrew Wiles, a researcher at Princeton, Cambridge claims to have 
    found a proof. 
 
    The proof was presented in Cambridge, UK during a three day seminar 
    to an audience including some of the leading experts in the field.
 
    The proof is long and cumbersome, but here are some of the first
    few details:
 
    *From Ken Ribet:
 
    Here is a brief summary of what Wiles said in his three lectures.
 
    The method of Wiles borrows results and techniques from lots and lots
    of people.  To mention a few: Mazur, Hida, Flach, Kolyvagin, yours
    truly, Wiles himself (older papers by Wiles), Rubin...  The way he does
    it is roughly as follows.  Start with a mod p representation of the
    Galois group of Q which is known to be modular.  You want to prove that
    all its lifts with a certain property are modular.  This means that the
    canonical map from Mazur's universal deformation ring to its "maximal
    Hecke algebra" quotient is an isomorphism.  To prove a map like this is
    an isomorphism, you can give some sufficient conditions based on
    commutative algebra.  Most notably, you have to bound the order of a
    cohomology group which looks like a Selmer group for Sym^2 of the
    representation attached to a modular form.  The techniques for doing
    this come from Flach; you also have to use Euler systems a la
    Kolyvagin, except in some new geometric guise.
    
    If you take an elliptic curve over Q, you can look at the
    representation of Gal on the 3-division points of the curve.  If you're
    lucky, this will be known to be modular, because of results of Jerry
    Tunnell (on base change).  Thus, if you're lucky, the problem I
    described above can be solved (there are most definitely some
    hypotheses to check), and then the curve is modular.  Basically, being
    lucky means that the image of the representation of Galois on
    3-division points is GL(2,Z/3Z).
    
    Suppose that you are unlucky, i.e., that your curve E has a rational
    subgroup of order 3.  Basically by inspection, you can prove that if it
    has a rational subgroup of order 5 as well, then it can't be
    semistable.  (You look at the four non-cuspidal rational points of
    X_0(15).)  So you can assume that E[5] is "nice." Then the idea is to
    find an E' with the same 5-division structure, for which E'[3] is
    modular.  (Then E' is modular, so E'[5] = E[5] is modular.)  You
    consider the modular curve X which parameterizes elliptic curves whose
    5-division points look like E[5].  This is a "twist" of X(5).  It's
    therefore of genus 0, and it has a rational point (namely, E), so it's
    a projective line.  Over that you look at the irreducible covering
    which corresponds to some desired 3-division structure.  You use
    Hilbert irreducibility and the Cebotarev density theorem (in some way
    that hasn't yet sunk in) to produce a non-cuspidal rational point of X
    over which the covering remains irreducible.  You take E' to be the
    curve corresponding to this chosen rational point of X.
    
    
    *From the previous version of the FAQ:
    
    (b) conjectures arising from the study of elliptic curves and
    modular forms. -- The Taniyama-Weil-Shmimura conjecture.
     
    There is a very important and well known conjecture known as the
    Taniyama-Weil-Shimura conjecture that concerns elliptic curves.
    This conjecture has been shown by the work of Frey, Serre, Ribet,
    et. al. to imply FLT uniformly, not just asymptotically as with the
    ABC conj.
    
    The conjecture basically states that all elliptic curves can be
    parameterized in terms of modular forms. 
 
    There is new work on the arithmetic of elliptic curves. Sha, the
    Tate-Shafarevich group on elliptic curves of rank 0 or 1. By the way
    an interesting aspect of this work is that there is a close 
    connection between Sha, and some of the classical work on FLT. For
    example, there is a classical proof that uses infinite descent to
    prove FLT for n = 4. It can be shown that there is an elliptic curve
    associated with FLT and that for n=4, Sha is trivial. It can also be
    shown that in the cases where Sha is non-trivial, that 
    infinite-descent arguments do not work; that in some sense 'Sha
    blocks the descent'. Somewhat more technically, Sha is an
    obstruction to the local-global principle [e.g. the Hasse-Minkowski
    theorem].
 
    *From Karl Rubin:
 
    Theorem.  If E is a semistable elliptic curve defined over Q,
      then E is modular.
 
    It has been known for some time, by work of Frey and Ribet, that
    Fermat follows from this.  If u^q + v^q + w^q = 0, then Frey had
    the idea of looking at the (semistable) elliptic curve
    y^2 = x(x-a^q)(x+b^q).  If this elliptic curve comes from a modular
    form, then the work of Ribet on Serre's conjecture shows that there
    would have to exist a modular form of weight 2 on Gamma_0(2).  But
    there are no such forms.
    
    To prove the Theorem, start with an elliptic curve E, a prime p and let
    
         rho_p : Gal(Q^bar/Q) -> GL_2(Z/pZ)
    
    be the representation giving the action of Galois on the p-torsion
    E[p].  We wish to show that a _certain_ lift of this representation
    to GL_2(Z_p) (namely, the p-adic representation on the Tate module
    T_p(E)) is attached to a modular form.  We will do this by using
    Mazur's theory of deformations, to show that _every_ lifting which
    'looks modular' in a certain precise sense is attached to a modular form.
    
    Fix certain 'lifting data', such as the allowed ramification,
    specified local behavior at p, etc. for the lift. This defines a
    lifting problem, and Mazur proves that there is a universal
    lift, i.e. a local ring R and a representation into GL_2(R) such
    that every lift of the appropriate type factors through this one.
    
    Now suppose that rho_p is modular, i.e. there is _some_ lift
    of rho_p which is attached to a modular form.  Then there is
    also a hecke ring T, which is the maximal quotient of R with the
    property that all _modular_ lifts factor through T.  It is a
    conjecture of Mazur that R = T, and it would follow from this
    that _every_ lift of rho_p which 'looks modular' (in particular the
    one we are interested in) is attached to a modular form.
    
    Thus we need to know 2 things:
 
      (a)  rho_p is modular
      (b)  R = T.
    
    It was proved by Tunnell that rho_3 is modular for every elliptic
    curve.  This is because PGL_2(Z/3Z) = S_4.  So (a) will be satisfied
    if we take p=3.  This is crucial.
    
    Wiles uses (a) to prove (b) under some restrictions on rho_p.  Using
    (a) and some commutative algebra (using the fact that T is Gorenstein,
    'basically due to Mazur')  Wiles reduces the statement T = R to
    checking an inequality between the sizes of 2 groups.  One of these
    is related to the Selmer group of the symmetric square of the given
    modular lifting of rho_p, and the other is related (by work of Hida)
    to an L-value.  The required inequality, which everyone presumes is
    an instance of the Bloch-Kato conjecture, is what Wiles needs to verify.
    
    He does this using a Kolyvagin-type Euler system argument.  This is
    the most technically difficult part of the proof, and is responsible
    for most of the length of the manuscript.  He uses modular
    units to construct what he calls a 'geometric Euler system' of
    cohomology classes.  The inspiration for his construction comes
    from work of Flach, who came up with what is essentially the
    'bottom level' of this Euler system.  But Wiles needed to go much
    farther than Flach did.  In the end, _under_certain_hypotheses_ on rho_p
    he gets a workable Euler system and proves the desired inequality.
    Among other things, it is necessary that rho_p is irreducible.
    
    Suppose now that E is semistable.
    
    Case 1.  rho_3 is irreducible.
    Take p=3.  By Tunnell's theorem (a) above is true.  Under these
    hypotheses the argument above works for rho_3, so we conclude
    that E is modular.
    
    Case 2.  rho_3 is reducible.
    Take p=5.  In this case rho_5 must be irreducible, or else E
    would correspond to a rational point on X_0(15).  But X_0(15)
    has only 4 noncuspidal rational points, and these correspond to
    non-semistable curves.  _If_ we knew that rho_5 were modular,
    then the computation above would apply and E would be modular.
    
    We will find a new semistable elliptic curve E' such that
    rho_{E,5} = rho_{E',5} and rho_{E',3} is irreducible.  Then
    by Case I, E' is modular.  Therefore rho_{E,5} = rho_{E',5}
    does have a modular lifting and we will be done.
    
    We need to construct such an E'.  Let X denote the modular
    curve whose points correspond to pairs (A, C) where A is an
    elliptic curve and C is a subgroup of A isomorphic to the group
    scheme E[5].  (All such curves will have mod-5 representation
    equal to rho_E.)  This X is genus 0, and has one rational point
    corresponding to E, so it has infinitely many.  Now Wiles uses a
    Hilbert Irreducibility argument to show that not all rational
    points can be images of rational points on modular curves
    covering X, corresponding to degenerate level 3 structure
    (i.e. im(rho_3) not GL_2(Z/3)).  In other words, an E' of the
    type we need exists.  (To make sure E' is semistable, choose
    it 5-adically close to E.  Then it is semistable at 5, and at
    other primes because rho_{E',5} = rho_{E,5}.)
    
 
    
2Q:  What are the values of:
 
 
largest known Mersenne prime?
 
A:  It is 2^756839-1. It was discovered by a Cray-2 in England in 1992.
    It has 227,832 digits.
 
	
largest known prime?
 
A:  The largest known prime is the Mersenne prime described above.
    The previous record holder, and the largest known non-Mersenne prime,
    is 391581*2^216193-1. See Brown, Noll, Parady, Smith, Smith, and
    Zarantonello, Letter to the editor, American Mathematical Monthly,
    vol. 97, 1990, p. 214. Throughout history, the largest known prime
    has almost always been a Mersenne prime; the period between Brown
    et al's discovery in Aug 1989 and Slowinski & Gage's in March 1992
    is one of the few exceptions.
 
	
largest known twin primes?
	
A:   The largest known twin primes are 1691232 * 1001 * 10^4020 +- 1,
     which is a number with 4030 digits, found by H. Dubner.
 
    The second largest known twin primes are 4650828 * 1001 * 10^3429 +- 1.
    They were found by H. Dubner
 
    References:
 
    B. K. Parady and J. F. Smith and S. E. Zarantonello,
    Smith, Noll and Brown.
    Largest known twin primes, Mathematics of Computation,
    vol.55, 1990, pp. 381-382. 
 
 
largest Fermat number with known factorization?
 
A:  F_11 = (2^(2^11)) + 1 which was  factored by Brent & Morain in
    1988. F9 = (2^(2^9)) + 1 = 2^512 + 1 was factored by 
    A.K. Lenstra, H.W. Lenstra Jr., M.S. Manasse & J.M. Pollard
    in 1990. The factorization for F10 is NOT known.
 
 
Are there good algorithms to factor a given integer?
 
A:  There are several that have subexponential estimated 
    running time, to mention just a few:
 
        Continued fraction algorithm,
        Class group method,
        Quadratic sieve algorithm,
        Elliptic curve algorithm,
        Number field sieve,
        Dixon's random squares algorithm,
        Valle's two-thirds algorithm,
        Seysen's class group algorithm,
 
    A.K. Lenstra, H.W. Lenstra Jr., "Algorithms in Number Theory",
    in: J. van Leeuwen (ed.), Handbook of Theoretical Computer 
    Science, Volume A: Algorithms and Complexity, Elsevier, pp. 
    673-715, 1990.
 
 
List of record numbers?
 
A:  Chris Caldwell maintains "THE LARGEST KNOWN PRIMES (ALL KNOWN
    PRIMES WITH 2000 OR MORE DIGITS)"-list. Send him mail to  
    [email protected] (preferred) or [email protected], on any new 
    gigantic primes (greater than 10,000 digits), titanic primes
    (greater than 1000 digits).
 
 
What is the current status on Mersenne primes?
 
A:  Mersenne primes are primes of the form 2^p-1. For 2^p-1 to be prime 
    we must have that p is prime. The following Mersenne primes are
    known.
 
    nr            p                                 year  by
    -----------------------------------------------------------------
     1-5   2,3,5,7,13                    in or before the middle ages
     6-7       17,19                     1588  Cataldi
     8          31                       1750  Euler
     9          61                       1883  Pervouchine
    10          89                       1911  Powers
    11          107                      1914  Powers
    12          127                      1876  Lucas
    13-14       521,607                  1952  Robinson
    15-17       1279,2203,2281           1952  Lehmer
    18          3217                     1957  Riesel
    19-20       4253,4423                1961  Hurwitz & Selfridge
    21-23       9689,9941,11213          1963  Gillies
    24          19937                    1971  Tuckerman
    25          21701                    1978  Noll & Nickel
    26          23209                    1979  Noll
    27          44497                    1979  Slowinski & Nelson
    28          86243                    1982  Slowinski
    29          110503                   1988  Colquitt & Welsh jr.
    30          132049                   1983  Slowinski
    31          216091                   1985  Slowinski
    32?         756839                   1992  Slowinski & Gage
 
    The way to determine if 2^p-1 is prime is to use the Lucas-Lehmer 
    test:
 
      Lucas_Lehmer_Test(p):
         u := 4
         for i from 3 to p do
            u := u^2-2 mod 2^p-1
         od
         if u == 0 then
            2^p-1 is prime
         else
            2^p-1 is composite
         fi
 
    The following ranges have been checked completely:
     2 - 355K and  430K - 520K
 
    More on Mersenne primes and the Lucas-Lehmer test can be found in:
 
     G.H. Hardy, E.M. Wright, An introduction to the theory of numbers,
     fifth edition, 1979, pp. 16, 223-225.
 
 
 
3Q.-  Formula for prime numbers...
 
 
     Is there a polynomial which gives all the prime numbers?
 
      No, there is not. This is a simple exercise to prove.
 
     Is there a non-constant polynomial that only takes on prime values?
 
      It has been proved that no such polynomial exists.
 
      The proof is simple enough that an high school student could probably
      discover it.  See, for example, Ribenboim's book _The Book of Prime
      Number Records_.
 
     Note, however, by the work of Jones, Sato, Wada, and Wiens, there *is* a
     polynomial in 26 variables such that the set of primes coincides with
     the set of *positive* values taken by this polynomial.  See Ribenboim,
     pp. 147-150.
 
     But most people would object to the term "formula" restricted to mean
     polynomial.  Can we not use summation signs, factorial, and the floor
     function in our "formula"?  If so, then indeed, there *are* formulas
     for the prime numbers.  Some of them are listed below.
 
     If we can't, then exactly what operations do you allow and why?
 
     Indeed, as I have previously argued, a reasonable interpretation of
     the word "formula" is simply "Turing machine that halts on all inputs".
     Under this interpretation, there certainly are halting Turing machines
     which compute the n'th prime number.  However, nobody knows how to
     compute the n'th prime in time polynomial in log n.  That's still
     an open question.
 
     Herb Wilf has addressed the question, "What is a formula?" in his
     delightful article, "What is an answer?" which appeared in the
     American Mathematical Monthly, 89 (1982), 289-292.  He draws the
     distinction between "formula" and "good formula".  Anyone who claims
     "there is no formula for the prime numbers" should read this article.
 
     Here are just a few articles that discuss "formulas" for primes.  Almost
     all of these do *not* require computation of the primes "ahead of time".
     Most of them rely on standard mathematical functions such as summation,
     factorial, greatest integer function, etc.
 
 
       C. Isenkrahe, Math. Annalen  53 (1900), 42-44.
 
       W. H. Mills, Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 53 (1947), 604.
 
       L. Moser, Math. Mag. 23 (1950), 163-164.
 
       E. M. Wright, Amer. Math. Monthly 58 (1951), 616-618.  (Correction,
      59 (1952), 99.)
 
       E. M. Wright, J. Lond. Math. Soc. 29 (1954), 63-71.
 
       B. R. Srinivasan, J. Indian Math. Soc. 25 (1961), 33-39.
 
       C. P. Willans, Math. Gazette 48 (1964), 413-415.
 
       V. C. Harris, Nordisk Mat. Tidskr. 17 (1969), 82.
 
       U. Dudley, Amer. Math. Monthly 76 (1969), 23-28.
 
       C. Vanden Eynden, Amer. Math. Monthly 79 (1972), 625.
 
       S. W. Golomb, Amer. Math. Monthly 81 (1974), 752-754.
 
 
      For more references see
 
       J.O. Shallit, E. Bach, _Algorithmic Number Theory_ (to be published,
       MIT Press).
 
 
4Q:  Where I can get pi up to a few hundred thousand digits of pi? 
    Does anyone have an algorithm to compute pi to those zillion 
    decimal places?
 
 
A:  MAPLE or MATHEMATICA can give you 10,000 digits of Pi in a blink,
    and they can compute another 20,000-1,000,000 overnight (range depends
    on hardware platform).
 
    It is possible to retrieve 1.25+ million digits of pi via anonymous
    ftp from the site wuarchive.wustl.edu, in the files pi.doc.Z and
    pi.dat.Z which reside in subdirectory doc/misc/pi.
 
    New York's Chudnovsky brothers have computed 2 billion digits of pi
    on a homebrew computer.
 
    How is pi calculated to many decimals ?
 
    There are essentially 3 different methods.
 
     1) One of the oldest is to use the power series expansion of atan(x)
     atan(x)=x-x^3/3+x^5/5-... together with formulas like
     pi=16*atan(1/5)-4*atan(1/239). This gives about 1.4 decimals per term.
 
     2) A second is to use formulas coming from Arithmetic-Geometric mean
     computations. A beautiful compendium of such formulas is given in the
     book of Borwein and Borwein: Pi and the AGM, Canadian Math. Soc. Series,
     John Wiley and Sons, New York, 1987. They have the advantage of converging
     quadratically, i.e. you double the number of decimals per iteration.
     For instance, to obtain 1 000 000 decimals, around 20 iterations are
     sufficient. The disadvantage is that you need FFT type multiplication
     to get a reasonable speed, and this is not so easy to program.
 
     3) A third one comes from the theory of complex multiplication of elliptic
     curves, and was discovered by S. Ramanujan. This gives a number of 
     beautiful formulas, but the most useful was missed by Ramanujan and 
     discovered by the Chudnovsky's. It is the following (slightly modified 
     for ease of programming):
 
     Set k1=545140134;k2=13591409;k3=640320;k4=100100025;k5=327843840;k6=53360;
 
     Then in AmsTeX notation
     
     $\pi=\frac{k6\sqrt(k3)}{S}$, where
 
     $$S=\sum_{n=0}^\infty (-1)^n\frac{(6n)!(k2+nk1)}{n!^3(3n)!(8k4k5)^n}$$
 
     The great advantages of this formula are that
 
     1) It converges linearly, but very fast (more than 14 decimal digits per
     term).
    
     2) The way it is written, all operations to compute S can be programmed
     very simply since it only involves multiplication/division by single
     precision numbers. This is why the constant 8k4k5 appearing in the 
     denominator has been written this way instead of 262537412640768000.
 
     This is how the Chudnovsky's have computed several billion decimals.
 
     Question: how can I get a C program which computes pi?
 
     Answer: if you are too lazy to use the hints above, you can use the
     following 160 character C program (who is the author of this?) which
     computes pi to 800 decimal digits. If you want more, it is easy to modify,
     but you have to understand how it works first.
 
     int a=10000,b,c=2800,d,e,f[2801],g;main(){for(;b-c;)f[b++]=a/5;
     for(;d=0,g=c*2;c-=14,printf("%.4d",e+d/a),e=d%a)for(b=c;d+=f[b]*a,
     f[b]=d%--g,d/=g--,--b;d*=b);}
 
 
 
 
    References :
 
    (This is a short version for a more comprehensive list contact
    Juhana Kouhia at [email protected])
 
    J. M. Borwein, P. B. Borwein, and D. H. Bailey, "Ramanujan,
    Modular Equations, and Approximations to Pi", American Mathematical
    Monthly, vol. 96, no. 3 (March 1989), p. 201 - 220.
 
    P. Beckman
    A history of pi
    Golem Press, CO, 1971 (fourth edition 1977)
 
    J.M. Borwein and P.B. Borwein
    The arithmetic-geometric mean and fast computation of elementary
    functions
    SIAM Review, Vol. 26, 1984, pp. 351-366
 
    J.M. Borwein and P.B. Borwein
    More quadratically converging algorithms for pi
    Mathematics of Computation, Vol. 46, 1986, pp. 247-253
 
    J.M. Borwein and P.B. Borwein
    Pi and the AGM - a study in analytic number theory and
    computational complexity
    Wiley, New York, 1987
 
    Shlomo Breuer and Gideon Zwas
    Mathematical-educational aspects of the computation of pi
    Int. J. Math. Educ. Sci. Technol., Vol. 15, No. 2, 1984,
    pp. 231-244
 
    David Chudnovsky and Gregory Chudnovsky
    The computation of classical constants, Columbia University, 
    Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA, Vol. 86, 1989.
 
    Y. Kanada and Y. Tamura
    Calculation of pi to 10,013,395 decimal places based on the
    Gauss-Legendre algorithm and Gauss arctangent relation
    Computer Centre, University of Tokyo, 1983
 
    Morris Newman and Daniel Shanks
    On a sequence arising in series for pi
    Mathematics of computation, Vol. 42, No. 165, Jan 1984,
    pp. 199-217
 
    E. Salamin
    Computation of pi using arithmetic-geometric mean
    Mathematics of Computation, Vol. 30, 1976, pp. 565-570
 
    D. Shanks and J.W. Wrench, Jr.
    Calculation of pi to 100,000 decimals
    Mathematics of Computation, Vol. 16, 1962, pp. 76-99
 
    Daniel Shanks
    Dihedral quartic approximations and series for pi
    J. Number Theory, Vol. 14, 1982, pp.397-423
 
    David Singmaster
    The legal values of pi
    The Mathematical Intelligencer, Vol. 7, No. 2, 1985
 
    Stan Wagon
    Is pi normal?
    The Mathematical Intelligencer, Vol. 7, No. 3, 1985
 
    J.W. Wrench, Jr.
    The evolution of extended decimal approximations to pi
    The Mathematics Teacher, Vol. 53, 1960, pp. 644-650
 
 
 
5Q:  Does there exist a number that is perfect and odd?
 
    A given number is perfect if it is equal to the sum of all its proper
    divisors. This question was first posed by Euclid in ancient Greece.
    This question is still open.  Euler proved that if  N  is an odd
    perfect number, then in the prime power decomposition of N, exactly
    one exponent is congruent to 1 mod 4 and all the other exponents are
    even. Furthermore, the prime occurring to an odd power must itself be
    congruent to 1 mod 4.  A sketch of the proof appears in Exercise 87,
    page 203 of Underwood Dudley's Elementary Number Theory, 2nd ed.
    It has been shown that there are no odd perfect numbers < 10^300.
 
 
 
Copyright Notice
 
Copyright (c) 1993   A. Lopez-Ortiz
 
 
--------------------------------------------------------------------------
Questions and Answers Edited and Compiled by:
 
Alex Lopez-Ortiz                              [email protected]
Department of Computer Science                      University of Waterloo
Waterloo, Ontario                                                   Canada
1817.2FAQ 2 of 3STAR::ABBASIonly 21 days to go and counting...Sat Nov 20 1993 01:06818
From: [email protected] (Alex Lopez-Ortiz)
Subject: sci.math: Frequently Asked Questions [2/3]
Organization: University of Waterloo
Date: Fri, 19 Nov 1993 14:03:38 GMT
Expires: Fri, 31 Dec 1993 14:03:28 GMT
 
Archive-Name: sci-math-faq/part2
Last-modified: October 26, 1993
Version: 5.0
 
 
This is a list of Frequently Asked Questions for sci.math (version 5.0).
Any contributions/suggestions/corrections are most welcome. Please use
* e-mail * on any comment concerning the FAQ list.
 
Section 2 of 3, questions 6Q to 18Q.
 
             Table of Contents
             -----------------
 1Q.- Fermat's Last Theorem, status of ..
 2Q.- Values of Record Numbers
 3Q.- Formula for prime numbers...
 4Q.- Digits of Pi, computation and references
 5Q.- Odd Perfect Number
 6Q.- Computer Algebra Systems, application of ..
 7Q.- Computer Algebra Systems, references to ..
 8Q.- Fields Medal, general info ..
 9Q.- Four Colour Theorem, proof of ..
10Q.- 0^0=1. A comprehensive approach
11Q.- 0.999... = 1. Properties of the real numbers ..
12Q.- There are three doors, The Monty Hall problem, Master Mind and
      other games ..
13Q.- Surface and Volume of the n-ball
14Q.- f(x)^f(x)=x, name of the function ..
15Q.- Projective plane of order 10 ..
16Q.- How to compute day of week of a given date
17Q.- Axiom of Choice and/or Continuum Hypothesis?
18Q.- Cutting a sphere into pieces of larger volume
19Q.- Pointers to Quaternions
20Q.- Erdos Number
21Q.- Why is there no Nobel in mathematics?
22Q.- General References and textbooks...
23Q.- Interest Rate...
24Q.- Euler's formula e^(i Pi) = - 1 ...
 
 
 
6Q:  I have this complicated symbolic problem (most likely
    a symbolic integral or a DE system) that I can't solve.
    What should I do?
 
A:  Find a friend with access to a computer algebra system
    like MAPLE, MACSYMA or MATHEMATICA and ask her/him to solve it.
    If packages cannot solve it, then (and only then) ask the net.
 
 
7Q:  Where can I get <Symbolic Computation Package>?
 
    THIS IS NOT A COMPREHENSIVE LIST. There are other Computer Algebra
    packages available that may better suit your needs. There is also
    a FAQ list in the group sci.math.symbolic. It includes a much larger
    list of vendors and developers. (The FAQ list can be obtained from
    math.berkeley.edu via anonymous ftp).
 
 
 
A: Maple
        Purpose: Symbolic and numeric computation, mathematical
        programming, and mathematical visualization.
        Contact: Waterloo Maple Software,
        450 Phillip Street
        Waterloo, Ontario
        N2L 5J2
        Phone (519)747-2373
        FAX   (519)747-5284
        email:  [email protected]
 
 
A: DOE-Macsyma
        Purpose: Symbolic and mathematical manipulations.
        Contact: National Energy Software Center
        Argonne National Laboratory 9700 South Cass Avenue
        Argonne, Illinois 60439
        Phone: (708) 972-7250
 
 
A: Pari
        Purpose: Number-theoretic computations and simple numerical
        analysis.
        Available for most 32-bit machines, including 386+387 and 486.
        This is a copyrighted but free package, available by ftp from
        math.ucla.edu (128.97.4.254) and ftp.inria.fr (128.93.1.26).
        Contact: questions about pari can be sent to [email protected]
        and for the Macintosh versions to [email protected]
 
 
A: Mathematica
        Purpose: Mathematical computation and visualization,
        symbolic programming.
        Contact: Wolfram Research, Inc.
        100 Trade Center Drive Champaign,
        IL 61820-7237
        Phone: 1-800-441-MATH
        [email protected]
 
 
A: Macsyma
        Purpose: Symbolic numerical and graphical mathematics.
        Contact: Macsyma Inc.
        20 Academy Street
        Arlington, MA 02174
        tel: 617-646-4550
        fax: 617-646-3161
        email: [email protected]
 
 
A: Matlab
        Purpose: `matrix laboratory' for tasks involving
        matrices, graphics and general numerical computation.
        Contact: The MathWorks, Inc.
        21 Prime Park Way
        Natick, MA 01760
        508-653-1415
        [email protected]
 
 
A: Cayley
        Purpose: Computation in algebraic and combinatorial structures
        such as groups, rings, fields, modules and graphs.
        Available for: SUN 3, SUN 4, IBM running AIX or VM, DEC VMS, others
        Contact: Computational Algebra Group
        University of Sydney
        NSW 2006
        Australia
        Phone:  (61) (02) 692 3338
        Fax: (61) (02) 692 4534
        [email protected]
 
 
8Q:  Let P be a property about the Fields Medal. Is P(x) true?
 
A:  Institution is meant to be the Institution to which the researcher
    in question was associated to at the time the medal was awarded.
 
 
Year Name               Birthplace              Age Institution
---- ----               ----------              --- -----------
1936 Ahlfors, Lars      Helsinki       Finland   29 Harvard U         USA
1936 Douglas, Jesse     New York NY    USA       39 MIT               USA
1950 Schwartz, Laurent  Paris          France    35 U of Nancy        France
1950 Selberg, Atle      Langesund      Norway    33 Adv.Std.Princeton USA
1954 Kodaira, Kunihiko  Tokyo          Japan     39 Princeton U       USA
1954 Serre, Jean-Pierre Bages          France    27 College de France France
1958 Roth, Klaus        Breslau        Germany   32 U of London       UK
1958 Thom, Rene         Montbeliard    France    35 U of Strasbourg   France
1962 Hormander, Lars    Mjallby        Sweden    31 U of Stockholm    Sweden
1962 Milnor, John       Orange NJ      USA       31 Princeton U       USA
1966 Atiyah, Michael    London         UK        37 Oxford U          UK
1966 Cohen, Paul        Long Branch NJ USA       32 Stanford U        USA
1966 Grothendieck, Alexander Berlin    Germany   38 U of Paris        France
1966 Smale, Stephen     Flint MI       USA       36 UC Berkeley       USA
1970 Baker, Alan        London         UK        31 Cambridge U       UK
1970 Hironaka, Heisuke  Yamaguchi-ken  Japan     39 Harvard U         USA
1970 Novikov, Serge     Gorki          USSR      32 Moscow U          USSR
1970 Thompson, John     Ottawa KA      USA       37 U of Chicago      USA
1974 Bombieri, Enrico   Milan          Italy     33 U of Pisa         Italy
1974 Mumford, David     Worth, Sussex  UK        37 Harvard U         USA
1978 Deligne, Pierre    Brussels       Belgium   33 IHES              France
1978 Fefferman, Charles Washington DC  USA       29 Princeton U       USA
1978 Margulis, Gregori  Moscow         USSR      32 InstPrblmInfTrans USSR
1978 Quillen, Daniel    Orange NJ      USA       38 MIT               USA
1982 Connes, Alain      Draguignan     France    35 IHES              France
1982 Thurston, William  Washington DC  USA       35 Princeton U       USA
1982 Yau, Shing-Tung    Kwuntung       China     33 IAS               USA
1986 Donaldson, Simon   Cambridge      UK        27 Oxford U          UK
1986 Faltings, Gerd     1954           Germany   32 Princeton U       USA
1986 Freedman, Michael  Los Angeles CA USA       35 UC San Diego      USA
1990 Drinfeld, Vladimir Kharkov        USSR      36 Phys.Inst.Kharkov USSR
1990 Jones, Vaughan     Gisborne       N Zealand 38 UC Berkeley       USA
1990 Mori, Shigefumi    Nagoya         Japan     39 U of Kyoto?       Japan
1990 Witten, Edward     Baltimore      USA       38 Princeton U/IAS   USA
 
References :
 
International Mathematical Congresses, An Illustrated History 1893-1986,
Revised Edition, Including 1986, by Donald J.Alberts, G. L. Alexanderson
and Constance Reid, Springer Verlag, 1987.
 
Tropp, Henry S., ``The origins and history of the Fields Medal,''
Historia Mathematica, 3(1976), 167-181.
 
 
9Q:  Has the Four Colour Theorem been proved?
 
    Four Color Theorem:
 
    Every planar map with regions of simple borders can be coloured
    with 4 colours in such a way that no two regions sharing a non-zero
    length border have the same colour.
 
A:  This theorem was proved with the aid of a computer in 1976.
    The proof shows that if aprox. 1,936  basic forms of maps
    can be coloured with four colours, then any given map can be
    coloured with four colours. A computer program coloured this
    basic forms. So far nobody has been able to prove it without
    using a computer. In principle it is possible to emulate the
    computer proof by hand computations.
 
    References:
 
    K. Appel and W. Haken, Every planar map is four colourable,
    Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 82, 1976
    pp.711-712.
 
    K. Appel and W. Haken, Every planar map is four colourable,
    Illinois Journal of Mathematics, vol. 21, 1977, pp. 429-567.
 
    T. Saaty and Paul Kainen, The Four Colour Theorem: Assault and
    Conquest, McGraw-Hill, 1977. Reprinted by Dover Publications 1986.
 
    K. Appel and W. Haken, Every Planar Map is Four Colourable,
    Contemporary Mathematics, vol. 98, American Mathematical Society,
    1989, pp.741.
 
    F. Bernhart, Math Reviews. 91m:05007, Dec. 1991. (Review of Appel
    and Haken's book).
 
 
10Q:  What is 0^0 ?
 
A:  According to some Calculus textbooks, 0^0 is an "indeterminate
    form". When evaluating a limit of the form 0^0, then you need
    to know that limits of that form are called "indeterminate forms",
    and that you need to use a special technique such as L'Hopital's
    rule to evaluate them. Otherwise, 0^0=1 seems to be the most
    useful choice for 0^0. This convention allows us to extend
    definitions in different areas of mathematics that otherwise would
    require treating 0 as a special case. Notice that 0^0 is a
    discontinuity of the function x^y.
 
    Rotando & Korn show that if f and g are real functions that vanish
    at the origin and are _analytic_ at 0 (infinitely differentiable is
    not sufficient), then f(x)^g(x) approaches 1 as x approaches 0 from
    the right.
 
    From Concrete Mathematics p.162 (R. Graham, D. Knuth, O. Patashnik):
 
    "Some textbooks leave the quantity 0^0 undefined, because the
    functions x^0 and 0^x have different limiting values when x
    decreases to 0. But this is a mistake. We must define
 
       x^0 = 1 for all x,
 
    if the binomial theorem is to be valid when x=0, y=0, and/or x=-y.
    The theorem is too important to be arbitrarily restricted! By
    contrast, the function 0^x is quite unimportant."
   Published by Addison-Wesley, 2nd printing Dec, 1988.
 
    References:
 
    H. E. Vaughan, The expression '0^0', Mathematics Teacher 63 (1970),
    pp.111-112.
 
    Louis M. Rotando & Henry Korn, "The Indeterminate Form 0^0",
    Mathematics Magazine, Vol. 50, No. 1 (January 1977), pp. 41-42.
 
    L. J. Paige, A note on indeterminate forms, American Mathematical
    Monthly, 61 (1954), 189-190; reprinted in the Mathematical
    Association of America's 1969 volume, Selected Papers on Calculus,
    pp. 210-211.
 
 
11Q:  Why is 0.9999... = 1?
 
A:  In modern mathematics, the string of symbols "0.9999..." is
    understood to be a shorthand for "the infinite sum  9/10 + 9/100
    + 9/1000 + ...." This in turn is shorthand for "the limit of the
    sequence of real numbers 9/10, 9/10 + 9/100, 9/10 + 9/100 + 9/1000,
    ..."  Using the well-known epsilon-delta definition of limit, one
    can easily show that this limit is 1.  The statement that
    0.9999...  = 1 is simply an abbreviation of this fact.
 
                    oo              m
                   ---   9         ---   9
        0.999... = >   ---- = lim  >   ----
                   --- 10^n  m->oo --- 10^n
                   n=1             n=1
 
 
        Choose epsilon > 0. Suppose delta = 1/-log_10 epsilon, thus
        epsilon = 10^(-1/delta). For every m>1/delta we have that
 
        |  m           |
        | ---   9      |     1          1
        | >   ---- - 1 | = ---- < ------------ = epsilon
        | --- 10^n     |   10^m   10^(1/delta)
        | n=1          |
 
        So by the (epsilon-delta) definition of the limit we have
 
               m
              ---   9
         lim  >   ---- = 1
        m->oo --- 10^n
              n=1
 
 
    An *informal* argument could be given by noticing that the following
    sequence of "natural" operations has as a consequence 1 = 0.9999....
    Therefore it's "natural" to assume 1 = 0.9999.....
 
             x = 0.99999....
           10x = 9.99999....
       10x - x = 9
            9x = 9
             x = 1
    Thus
             1 = 0.99999....
 
    References:
 
    E. Hewitt & K. Stromberg, Real and Abstract Analysis,
    Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1965.
 
    W. Rudin, Principles of Mathematical Analysis, McGraw-Hill, 1976.
 
 
12Q:  There are three doors, and there is a car hidden behind one
    of them, Master Mind and other games ..
 
A:  Read frequently asked questions from rec.puzzles, as well as
    their ``archive file'' where the problem is solved and carefully 
    explained. (The Monty Hall problem). 
 
    MANY OTHER MATHEMATICAL GAMES ARE EXPLAINED IN THE REC.PUZZLES 
    FAQ AND ARCHIVES. READ IT BEFORE ASKING IN SCI.MATH.
 
    Your chance of winning is 2/3 if you switch and 1/3 if you don't.
    For a full explanation from the rec.puzzles' archive, send to the
    address [email protected] an email message consisting 
    of the text
 
               send monty.hall
 
 
    Also any other FAQ list can be obtained through anonymous ftp from
    rtfm.mit.edu.
 
    References
 
    American Mathematical Monthly, January 1992.
 
 
    For the game of Master Mind it has been proven that no more than
    five moves are required in the worst case. For references look at
 
    One such algorithm was published in the Journal of Recreational
    Mathematics; in '70 or '71 (I think), which always solved the
    4 peg problem in 5 moves. Knuth later published an algorithm which
    solves the problem in a shorter # of moves - on average - but can
    take six guesses on certain combinations.
 
 
 
    Donald E. Knuth, The Computer as Master Mind, J. Recreational Mathematics
    9 (1976-77), 1-6.
 
 
13Q:  What is the formula for the "Surface Area" of a sphere in
    Euclidean N-Space.  That is, of course, the volume of the N-1
    solid which comprises the boundary of an N-Sphere.
 
A:  The volume of a ball is the easiest formula to remember:  It's r^N
    times pi^(N/2)/(N/2)!.  The only hard part is taking the factorial
    of a half-integer.  The real definition is that x! = Gamma(x+1), but
    if you want a formula, it's:
 
    (1/2+n)! = sqrt(pi)*(2n+2)!/(n+1)!/4^(n+1)
 
    To get the surface area, you just differentiate to get
    N*pi^(N/2)/(N/2)!*r^(N-1).
 
    There is a clever way to obtain this formula using Gaussian
    integrals. First, we note that the integral over the line of
    e^(-x^2) is sqrt(pi).  Therefore the integral over N-space of
    e^(-x_1^2-x_2^2-...-x_N^2) is sqrt(pi)^n.  Now we change to
    spherical coordinates.  We get the integral from 0 to infinity
    of V*r^(N-1)*e^(-r^2), where V is the surface volume of a sphere.
    Integrate by parts repeatedly to get the desired formula.
 
    It is possible to derive the volume of the sphere from ``first 
    principles''.
 
 
14Q:  Does anyone know a name (or a closed form) for
 
      f(x)^f(x)=x
 
 
    Solving for f one finds a "continued fraction"-like answer
 
 
               f(x) = log x
                      -----
                      log (log x
                          ------
                              ...........
 
A:  This question has been repeated here from time to time over the
    years, and no one seems to have heard of any published work on it,
    nor a published name for it (D. Merrit proposes "lx" due to its
    (very) faint resemblance to log). It's not an analytic function.
 
    The "continued fraction" form for its numeric solution is highly
    unstable in the region of its minimum at 1/e (because the graph is
    quite flat there yet logarithmic approximation oscillates wildly),
    although it converges fairly quickly elsewhere. To compute its value
    near 1/e, use the bisection method which gives good results. Bisection
    in other regions converges much more slowly than the "logarithmic
    continued fraction" form, so a hybrid of the two seems suitable.
    Note that it's dual valued for the reals (and many valued complex
    for negative reals).
 
    A similar function is a "built-in" function in MAPLE called W(x).
    MAPLE considers a solution in terms of W(x) as a closed form (like
    the erf function). W is defined as W(x)*exp(W(x))=x.
 
    An extensive treatise on the known facts of Lambert's W function
    is available for anonymous ftp at daisy.uwaterloo.ca in the
    maple/5.2/doc/LambertW.ps.
 
 
 
15Q: Does there exist a projective plane of order 10?
 
    More precisely:
 
    Is it possible to define 111 sets (lines) of 11 points each
    such that:
    
      For any pair of points there is precisely one line containing them
      both and for any pair of lines there is only one point common to
      them both?
 
 
A:  Analogous questions with n^2 + n + 1 and n + 1 instead of 111 and 11
    have been positively answered only in case n is a prime power.
    For n=6 it is not possible, more generally if n is congruent to 1
    or 2 mod 4 and can not be written as a sum of two squares, then an
    FPP of order n does not exist.  The n=10 case has been settled as not
    possible either by Clement Lam. As the "proof" took several years of
    computer search (the equivalent of 2000 hours on a Cray-1) it can be 
    called the most time-intensive computer assisted single proof. The
    final steps were ready in January 1989.
 
    References
 
    R. H. Bruck and H. J. Ryser, "The nonexistence of certain finite
    projective planes," Canadian Journal of Mathematics, vol. 1 (1949),
    pp 88-93.
 
    C. Lam, Amer.Math.Monthly 98 (1991), 305-318.
 
 
16Q:  Is there a formula to determine the day of the week, given
    the month, day and year?
 
A:  First a brief explanation: In the Gregorian Calendar, over a period
    of four hundred years, there are 97 leap years and 303 normal years.
    Each normal year, the day of January 1 advances by one; for each leap
    year it advances by two.
    
        303 + 97 + 97 = 497 = 7 * 71
 
    As a result, January 1 year N occurs on the same day of the week as
    January 1 year N + 400.  Because the leap year pattern also recurs
    with a four hundred year cycle, a simple table of four hundred
    elements, and single modulus, suffices to determine the day of the
    week (in the Gregorian Calendar), and does it much faster than all the
    other algorithms proposed.  Also, each element takes (in principle)
    only three bits; the entire table thus takes only 1200 bits, or 300
    bytes; on many computers this will be less than the instructions to do
    all the complicated calculations proposed for the other algorithms.
 
    The Julian Calendar has a four year cycle of leap years; after four
    years January 1 has advanced by 5 days.  Since 5 is relatively prime
    to 7, a table of 35 elements is necessary.
 
    Incidental note: Because 7 does not divide 400, January 1 occurs more
    frequently on some days than others (in the Gregorian calendar, of
    course)!  Trick your friends!
 
    In a cycle of four hundred years, January 1 and March 1 occur on the
    following days with the following frequencies:
    
           Sun      Mon     Tue     Wed     Thu     Fri     Sat
    Jan 1: 58       56      58      57      57      58      56
    Mar 1: 58       56      58      56      58      57      57
 
    Of interest is that (contrary to most initial guesses) the occurrence
    is not maximally flat.
 
    Here is the standard method.
 
     A. Take the last two digits of the year.
     B. Divide by 4, discarding any fraction.
     C. Add the day of the month.
     D. Add the month's key value: JFM AMJ JAS OND
                                   144 025 036 146
     E. Subtract 1 for January or February of a leap year.
     F. For a Gregorian date, add 0 for 1900's, 6 for 2000's, 4 for 1700's, 2
           for 1800's; for other years, add or subtract multiples of 400.
     G. For a Julian date, add 1 for 1700's, and 1 for every additional
      century you go back.
     H. Add the last two digits of the year.
 
    Now take the remainder when you divide by 7; 1 is Sunday, the first day
    of the week, 2 is Monday, and so on.
 
    Another formula is:
 
    W == k + [2.6m - 0.2] - 2C + Y + [Y/4] + [C/4]     mod 7
       where [] denotes the integer floor function (round down),
       k is day (1 to 31)
       m is month (1 = March, ..., 10 = December, 11 = Jan, 12 = Feb)
                     Treat Jan & Feb as months of the preceding year
       C is century ( 1987 has C = 19)
       Y is year    ( 1987 has Y = 87 except Y = 86 for jan & feb)
       W is week day (0 = Sunday, ..., 6 = Saturday)
 
    This formula is good for the Gregorian calendar
    (introduced 1582 in parts of Europe, adopted in 1752 in Great Britain
    and its colonies, and on various dates in other countries).
 
    It handles century & 400 year corrections, but there is still a
    3 day / 10,000 year error which the Gregorian calendar does not take.
    into account.  At some time such a correction will have to be
    done but your software will probably not last that long :-)   !
 
 
    References:
 
    Winning Ways  by Conway, Guy, Berlekamp is supposed to have it.
 
    Martin Gardner in "Mathematical Carnival".
 
    Michael Keith and Tom Craver, "The Ultimate Perpetual Calendar?",
    Journal of Recreational Mathematics, 22:4, pp. 280-282, 19
 
    K. Rosen, "Elementary Number Theory",  p. 156.
 
 
 
17Q:  What is the Axiom of Choice?  Why is it important? Why some articles
    say "such and such is provable, if you accept the axiom of choice."?
    What are the arguments for and against the axiom of choice?
 
 
A:  There are several equivalent formulations:
 
    -The Cartesian product of nonempty sets is nonempty, even
    if the product is of an infinite family of sets.
 
    -Given any set S of mutually disjoint nonempty sets, there is a set C
    containing a single member from each element of S.  C can thus be
    thought of as the result of "choosing" a representative from each
    set in S. Hence the name.
 
    >Why is it important?
 
    All kinds of important theorems in analysis require it.  Tychonoff's
    theorem and the Hahn-Banach theorem are examples. Indeed,
    Tychonoff's theorem is equivalent to AC. Similarly, AC is equivalent
    to the thesis that every set can be well-ordered.  Zermelo's first
    proof of this in 1904 I believe was the first proof in which AC was
    made explicit.  AC is especially handy for doing infinite cardinal
    arithmetic, as without it the most you get is a *partial* ordering
    on the cardinal numbers.  It also enables you to prove such
    interesting general facts as that n^2 = n for all infinite cardinal
    numbers.
 
    > What are the arguments for and against the axiom of choice?
 
    The axiom of choice is independent of the other axioms of set theory
    and can be assumed or not as one chooses.
 
    (For) All ordinary mathematics uses it.
 
    There are a number of arguments for AC, ranging from a priori to
    pragmatic.  The pragmatic argument (Zermelo's original approach) is
    that it allows you to do a lot of interesting mathematics.  The more
    conceptual argument derives from the "iterative" conception of set
    according to which sets are "built up" in layers, each layer consisting
    of all possible sets that can be constructed out of elements in the
    previous layers.  (The building up is of course metaphorical, and is
    suggested only by the idea of sets in some sense consisting of their
    members; you can't have a set of things without the things it's a set
    of).  If then we consider the first layer containing a given set S of
    pairwise disjoint nonempty sets, the argument runs, all the elements
    of all the sets in S must exist at previous levels "below" the level
    of S.  But then since each new level contains *all* the sets that can
    be formed from stuff in previous levels, it must be that at least by
    S's level all possible choice sets have already been *formed*. This
    is more in the spirit of Zermelo's later views (c. 1930).
 
    (Against) It has some supposedly counterintuitive consequences,
    such as the Banach-Tarski paradox. (See next question)
 
    Arguments against AC typically target its nonconstructive character:
    it is a cheat because it conjures up a set without providing any
    sort of *procedure* for its construction--note that no *method* is
    assumed for picking out the members of a choice set.  It is thus the
    platonic axiom par excellence, boldly asserting that a given set
    will always exist under certain circumstances in utter disregard of
    our ability to conceive or construct it.  The axiom thus can be seen
    as marking a divide between two opposing camps in the philosophy of
    mathematics:  those for whom mathematics is essentially tied to our
    conceptual capacities, and hence is something we in some sense
    *create*, and those for whom mathematics is independent of any such
    capacities and hence is something we *discover*.  AC is thus of
    philosophical as well as mathematical significance.
 
 
    It should be noted that some interesting mathematics has come out of an
    incompatible axiom, the Axiom of Determinacy (AD).  AD asserts that
    any two-person game without ties has a winning strategy for the first or
    second player.  For finite games, this is an easy theorem; for infinite
    games with duration less than \omega and move chosen from a countable set,
    you can prove the existence of a counter-example using AC.  Jech's book
    "The Axiom of Choice" has a discussion.
 
    An example of such a game goes as follows.
 
       Choose in advance a set of infinite sequences of integers; call it A.
       Then I pick an integer, then you do, then I do, and so on forever
       (i.e. length \omega).  When we're done, if the sequence of integers
       we've chosen is in A, I win; otherwise you win.  AD says that one of
       us must have a winning strategy.  Of course the strategy, and which
       of us has it, will depend upon A.
 
 
    From a philosophical/intuitive/pedagogical standpoint, I think Bertrand
    Russell's shoe/sock analogy has a lot to recommend it.  Suppose you have an
    infinite collection of pairs of shoes.  You want to form a set with one
    shoe from each pair.  AC is not necessary, since you can define the set as
    "the set of all left shoes". (Technically, we're using the axiom of
    replacement, one of the basic axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) set theory.)
    If instead you want to form a set containing one sock from each pair of an
    infinite collection of pairs of socks, you now need AC.
 
 
    References:
 
    Maddy, "Believing the Axioms, I", J. Symb. Logic, v. 53, no. 2, June 1988,
    pp. 490-500, and "Believing the Axioms II" in v.53, no. 3.
 
    Gregory H. Moore, Zermelo's Axiom of Choice, New York, Springer-Verlag,
    1982.
 
    H. Rubin and J. E. Rubin, Equivalents of the Axiom of Choice II,
    North-Holland/Elsevier Science, 1985.
 
    A. Fraenkel, Y.  Bar-Hillel, and A. Levy, Foundations of Set Theory,
    Amsterdam, North-Holland, 1984 (2nd edition, 2nd printing), pp. 53-86.
 
 
18Q:  Cutting a sphere into pieces of larger volume. Is it possible
    to cut a sphere into a finite number of pieces and reassemble
    into a solid of twice the volume?
 
A:  This question has many variants and it is best answered explicitly.
    Given two polygons of the same area, is it always possible to
    dissect one into a finite number of pieces which can be reassembled
    into a replica of the other?
 
    Dissection theory is extensive.  In such questions one needs to
    specify
 
     (A) what a "piece" is,  (polygon?  Topological disk?  Borel-set?
         Lebesgue-measurable set?  Arbitrary?)
 
     (B) how many pieces are permitted (finitely many? countably? uncountably?)
 
     (C) what motions are allowed in "reassembling" (translations?
         rotations?  orientation-reversing maps?  isometries?
         affine maps?  homotheties?  arbitrary continuous images?  etc.)
 
     (D) how the pieces are permitted to be glued together.  The
         simplest notion is that they must be disjoint.  If the pieces
         are polygons [or any piece with a nice boundary] you can permit
         them to be glued along their boundaries, ie the interiors of the
         pieces disjoint, and their union is the desired figure.
 
 
    Some dissection results
 
     1) We are permitted to cut into FINITELY MANY polygons, to TRANSLATE
        and ROTATE the pieces, and to glue ALONG BOUNDARIES;
        then Yes, any two equal-area polygons are equi-decomposable.
 
        This theorem was proven by Bolyai and Gerwien independently, and has
        undoubtedly been independently rediscovered many times.  I would not
        be surprised if the Greeks knew this.
 
        The Hadwiger-Glur theorem implies that any two equal-area polygons are
        equi-decomposable using only TRANSLATIONS and ROTATIONS BY 180
        DEGREES.
 
     2) THM (Hadwiger-Glur, 1951) Two equal-area polygons P,Q are
        equi-decomposable by TRANSLATIONS only, iff we have equality of these
        two functions:     PHI_P() = PHI_Q()
        Here, for each direction v (ie, each vector on the unit circle in the
        plane), let PHI_P(v) be the sum of the lengths of the edges of P which
        are perpendicular to v, where for such an edge, its length is positive
        if v is an outward normal to the edge and is negative if v is an
        inward normal to the edge.
 
 
     3) In dimension 3, the famous "Hilbert's third problem" is:
 
       "If P and Q are two polyhedra of equal volume, are they
        equi-decomposable by means of translations and rotations, by
        cutting into finitely many sub-polyhedra, and gluing along
        boundaries?"
 
        The answer is "NO" and was proven by Dehn in 1900, just a few months
        after the problem was posed. (Ueber raumgleiche polyeder, Goettinger
        Nachrichten 1900, 345-354). It was the first of Hilbert's problems
        to be solved. The proof is nontrivial but does *not* use the axiom
        of choice.
 
        "Hilbert's Third Problem", by V.G.Boltianskii, Wiley 1978.
 
 
     4) Using the axiom of choice on non-countable sets, you can prove
        that a solid sphere can be dissected into a finite number of
        pieces that can be reassembled to two solid spheres, each of
        same volume of the original. No more than nine pieces are needed.
 
        The minimum possible number of pieces is FIVE.  (It's quite easy
        to show that four will not suffice).  There is a particular
        dissection in which one of the five pieces is the single center
        point of the original sphere, and the other four pieces  A, A',
        B, B'  are such that A is congruent to A' and B is congruent to B'.
        [See Wagon's book].
 
        This construction is known as the "Banach-Tarski" paradox or the
        "Banach-Tarski-Hausdorff" paradox (Hausdorff did an early version of
        it).  The "pieces" here are non-measurable sets, and they are
        assembled *disjointly* (they are not glued together along a boundary,
        unlike the situation in Bolyai's thm.)
         An excellent book on Banach-Tarski is:
 
        "The Banach-Tarski Paradox", by Stan Wagon, 1985, Cambridge
        University Press.
 
        Robert M. French, The Banach-Tarski theorem, The Mathematical 
        Intelligencer 10 (1988) 21-28.
 
 
        The pieces are not (Lebesgue) measurable, since measure is preserved
        by rigid motion. Since the pieces are non-measurable, they do not
        have reasonable boundaries. For example, it is likely that each piece's
        topological-boundary is the entire ball.
 
        The full Banach-Tarski paradox is stronger than just doubling the
        ball.  It states:
 
     5) Any two bounded subsets (of 3-space) with non-empty interior, are
        equi-decomposable by translations and rotations.
 
        This is usually illustrated by observing that a pea can be cut up
        into finitely pieces and reassembled into the Earth.
 
        The easiest decomposition "paradox" was observed first by Hausdorff:
 
     6) The unit interval can be cut up into COUNTABLY many pieces which,
        by *translation* only, can be reassembled into the interval of
        length 2.
 
        This result is, nowadays, trivial, and is the standard example of a
        non-measurable set, taught in a beginning graduate class on measure
        theory.
 
 
        References:
 
        In addition to Wagon's book above, Boltyanskii has written at least
        two works on this subject.  An elementary one is:
 
          "Equivalent and equidecomposable figures"
 
        in Topics in Mathematics published by D.C. HEATH AND CO., Boston.  It
        is a translation from the 1956 work in Russian.
 
          Also, the article "Scissor Congruence" by Dubins, Hirsch and ?,
        which appeared about 20 years ago in the Math Monthly, has a pretty
        theorem on decomposition by Jordan arcs.
 
 
        ``Banach and Tarski had hoped that the physical absurdity of this
        theorem would encourage mathematicians to discard AC. They were
        dismayed when the response of the math community was `Isn't AC great?
        How else could we get such counterintuitive results?' ''
 
 
 
Copyright Notice
 
Copyright (c) 1993   A. Lopez-Ortiz
 
 
--------------------------------------------------------------------------
Questions and Answers Edited and Compiled by:
 
Alex Lopez-Ortiz                              [email protected]
Department of Computer Science                      University of Waterloo
Waterloo, Ontario                                                   Canada
1817.3FAQ 3 of 3STAR::ABBASIonly 21 days to go and counting...Sat Nov 20 1993 01:07420
From: [email protected] (Alex Lopez-Ortiz)
Subject: sci.math: Frequently Asked Questions [3/3]
Organization: University of Waterloo
Date: Fri, 19 Nov 1993 14:03:43 GMT
Expires: Fri, 31 Dec 1993 14:03:28 GMT
 
Archive-Name: sci-math-faq/part3
Last-modified: October 12, 1993
Version: 5.0
 
 
This is a list of Frequently Asked Questions for sci.math (version 5.0).
Any contributions/suggestions/corrections are most welcome. Please use
* e-mail * on any comment concerning the FAQ list.
 
Section 3 of 3, questions 19Q to 24Q.
 
             Table of Contents
             -----------------
 
 
 1Q.- Fermat's Last Theorem, status of ..
 2Q.- Values of Record Numbers
 3Q.- Formula for prime numbers...
 4Q.- Digits of Pi, computation and references
 5Q.- Odd Perfect Number
 6Q.- Computer Algebra Systems, application of ..
 7Q.- Computer Algebra Systems, references to ..
 8Q.- Fields Medal, general info ..
 9Q.- Four Colour Theorem, proof of ..
10Q.- 0^0=1. A comprehensive approach
11Q.- 0.999... = 1. Properties of the real numbers ..
12Q.- There are three doors, The Monty Hall problem, Master Mind and
      other games ..
13Q.- Surface and Volume of the n-ball
14Q.- f(x)^f(x)=x, name of the function ..
15Q.- Projective plane of order 10 ..
16Q.- How to compute day of week of a given date
17Q.- Axiom of Choice and/or Continuum Hypothesis?
18Q.- Cutting a sphere into pieces of larger volume
19Q.- Pointers to Quaternions
20Q.- Erdos Number
21Q.- Why is there no Nobel in mathematics?
22Q.- General References and textbooks...
23Q.- Interest Rate...
24Q.- Euler's formula e^(i Pi) = - 1 ...
 
 
 
 
 
19Q: Is there a theory of quaternionic analytic functions, that is, a four-
    dimensional analog to the theory of complex analytic functions?
    
A.  Yes. This was developed in the 1930s by the mathematician Fueter.
    It is based on a generalization of the Cauchy-Riemann equations,
    since the possible alternatives of power series expansions or
    quaternion differentiability do not produce useful theories. A number
    of useful integral theorems follow from the theory. Sudbery provides
    an excellent review. Deavours covers some of the same material less
    thoroughly.  Brackx discusses a further generalization to arbitrary 
    Clifford algebras.
 
      Anthony Sudbery, Quaternionic Analysis, Proc. Camb. Phil. Soc.,
      vol. 85, pp 199-225, 1979.
 
      Cipher A. Deavours, The Quaternion Calculus, Am. Math. Monthly,
      vol. 80, pp 995-1008, 1973.
 
      F. Brackx and R. Delanghe and F. Sommen, Clifford analysis,
      Pitman, 1983.
 
 
20Q: What is the Erdos Number?
 
    Form an undirected graph where the vertices are academics, and an
    edge connects academic X to academic Y if X has written a paper
    with Y. The Erdos number of X is the length of the shortest path
    in this graph connecting X with Erdos.
 
    What is the Erdos Number of X ? for a few selected X in {Math,physics}
 
    Erdos has Erdos number 0.  Co-authors of Erdos have Erdos number 1.
    Einstein has Erdos number 2, since he wrote a paper with Ernst Straus,
    and Straus wrote many papers with Erdos.
 
    Why people care about it?
 
     Nobody seems to have a reasonable answer...
 
    Who is Paul Erdos? 
 
    Paul Erdos is an Hungarian mathematician, he obtained his PhD
    from the University of Manchester and has spent most of his 
    efforts tackling "small" problems and conjectures related to
    graph theory, combinatorics, geometry and number theory.
 
    He is one of the most prolific publishers of papers; and is
    also and indefatigable traveller.
 
 
    References:
 
     Caspar Goffman, And what is your Erdos number?, American Mathematical
     Monthly v. 76 (1969), p. 791.
 
 
21Q: Why is there no Nobel in mathematics? #
 
    Nobel prizes were created by the will of Alfred Nobel, a notable
    swedish chemist.
 
    One of the most common --and unfounded-- reasons as to why Nobel
    decided against a Nobel prize in math is that [a woman he proposed
    to/his wife/his mistress] [rejected him beacuse of/cheated him
    with] a famous mathematician. Gosta Mittag-Leffler is often claimed
    to be the guilty party.
     
    There is no historical evidence to support the story.
 
    For one, Mr. Nobel was never married.
 
    There are more credible reasons as to why there is no Nobel prize
    in math. Chiefly among them is simply the fact he didn't care much
    for mathematics, and that it was not considered a practical 
    science from which humanity could benefit (a chief purpose
    for creating the Nobel Foundation).
 
 
    Here are some relevant facts:
 
    1. Nobel never married, hence no ``wife''. (He did have a mistress,
    a Viennese woman named Sophie Hess.)
 
    2. Gosta Mittag-Leffler was an important mathematician in Sweden
    in the late 19th-early 20th century.  He was the founder of the
    journal Acta Mathematica, played an important role in helping the
    career of Sonya Kovalevskaya, and was eventually head of the
    Stockholm Hogskola, the precursor to Stockholms Universitet.
    However, it seems highly unlikely that he would have been a
    leading candidate for an early Nobel Prize in mathematics, had 
    there been one -- there were guys like Poincare and Hilbert around,
    after all.
 
    3.  There is no evidence that Mittag-Leffler had much contact with
    Alfred Nobel (who resided in Paris during the latter part of his
    life), still less that there was animosity between them for whatever
    reason.  To the contrary, towards the end of Nobel's life 
    Mittag-Leffler was engaged in ``diplomatic'' negotiations to try to
    persuade Nobel to designate a substantial part of his fortune to the
    Hogskola. It seems hardly likely that he would have undertaken this
    if there was prior bad blood between them.  Although initially Nobel
    seems to have intended to do this, eventually he came up with the
    Nobel Prize idea -- much to the disappointment of the Hogskola,
    not to mention Nobel's relatives and Fraulein Hess.
 
    According to the very interesting study by Elisabeth Crawford,
    ``The Beginnings of the Nobel Institution'', Cambridge Univ. Press,
    1984, pages 52-53:
 
    ``Although it is not known how those in responsible positions
    at the Hogskola came to believe that a *large* bequest was forthcoming,
    this indeed was the expectation, and the disappointment was keen when
    it was announced early in 1897 that the Hogskola had been left out of
    Nobel's final will in 1895.  Recriminations followed, with both
    Pettersson and Arrhenius [academic rivals of Mittag-Leffler in the
    administration of the Hogskola] letting it be known that Nobel's
    dislike for Mittag-Leffler had brought about what Pettersson termed the
    `Nobel Flop'.  This is only of interest because it may have contributed
    to the myth that Nobel had planned to institute a prize in mathematics
    but had refrained because of his antipathy to Mittag-Leffler or
    --in another version of the same story-- because of their rivalry for
    the affections of a woman....''
 
    4.  A final speculation concerning the psychological element.
    Would Nobel, sitting down to draw up his testament, presumably
    in a mood of great benevolence to mankind, have allowed a mere
    personal grudge to distort his idealistic plans for the monument
    he would leave behind?
 
    Nobel, an inventor and industrialist, did not create a prize in
    mathematics simply because he was not particularly interested
    in mathematics or theoretical science.  His will speaks of
    prizes for those ``inventions or discoveries'' of greatest
    practical benefit to mankind.  (Probably as a result of this 
    language, the physics prize has been awarded for experimental work
    much more often than for advances in theory.)
 
    However, the story of some rivalry over a woman is obviously
    much more amusing, and that's why it will probably continue to
    be repeated.
 
   
    References:
 
     Mathematical Intelligencer, vol. 7 (3), 1985, p. 74.
 
     Elisabeth Crawford, ``The Beginnings of the Nobel Institution'', 
     Cambridge Univ. Press, 1984.
 
 
22Q: General References and textbooks... 
 
 
     Full references and/or title suggestions will be appreciated:
     Algebra: 
 
     Lang, Serge. Algebra
     Birkhoff, McLane, Algebra
 
     Analysis:
 
     Rudin
     Hewitt, Stromberg
 
 
 
 
23Q: Here's a formula which can be used in 123, Excel, Wings and
    Dynaplan:
 
     ------- Input this data -------------------------------
     principal amount = E9                  ( in dollars )
     Amortization Period = d10              ( in years ie 6 mon = .5 )
     Payments / year = D11                  ( 12 = monthly, 52 = weekly )
     Published Interest rate = D12          ( ie 9 % = 0.09 )
     Times per year Int calculated = d13    ( CDN mortgage use 2
                                         US mortgage use 12
                                         all other loans use 12 )
     ----- Calculate the proper rate of interest -----------
 
     e14 = Effective annual rate = EXP(D13*LN(1+(D12/D13)))-1
     e15 = Interest rate per payment = (EXP(LN(E14+1)/(D10*D11))-1)*D10*D11
 
     e17 = Payments = APMT(E9,E15/D11,D10*D11) ( both these functions are
                    = PMT (E9,E15/D11,D10*D11) ( indentical,diff spreadsheet)
           APMT( principal amount,interest rate per period,# periods )
           ( this is a standard function on any true commercial spreadsheet)
 
           OR use the following if done using a calulator
         = Payments = P*I/[1-(I+1)^-T]
                    = E9*(E15/D11)/(1-((E15/D11) +1)**(-1*D10*D11))
 
     Total interest cost = E17*D10*D11-E9
 
     -- Use these formulas if you wish to generate an amortization table --
     always add up to 'Payments (e17)'
     Interest per payment  = current balance * ( E15 / D11 )
     Principal per payment = current balance - Interest per payment
     new current balance   = current balance - Principal per payment -
                             (extra payment)
 
        keep repeating until 'new current balance' = 0
 
 
 
            Derivation of Compound Interest Rate Formula
 
     Suppose you deposited a fixed payment into an interest bearing
     account at regular intervals, say monthly, at the end of each month.
     How much money would there be in the account at the end of the nth
     month (at which point you've made n payments)?
 
     Let i be the monthly interest rate as a fraction of principle.
 
     Let x be the amount deposited each month.
 
     Let n be the total number of months.
 
     Let p[k] be the principle after k months.
 
     So the recursive formula is:
 
          p[n] = x + ( (1 + i) * p[n-1] )                  eq 1
 
     This yields the summation:
 
                 n-1
                 ---
                 \
          p[n] = /  x * (1 + i)^k                          eq 2
                 ---
                 k=0
 
     The way to solve this is to multiply through by (1 + i) and
     subtract the original equation from the resulting equation.
     Observe that all terms in the summation cancel except the
     last term of the multiplied equation and the first term of
     the original equation:
 
 
          i * p[n] = x * ( (1 + i)^n - 1)                  eq 3
 
     or
 
          p[n] = x * ( (1 + i)^n - 1) / i                  eq 4
 
     Now suppose you borrow p at constant interest rate i.
     You make monthly payments of x.  It turns out that this problem
     is identical to taking out a balloon loan of p (that is it's
     all due at the end of some term) and putting payments of x
     into a savings account.  At the end of the term you use the
     principle in the savings account to pay off the balance of
     the loan.  The loan and the savings account, of course, must
     be at the same interest rate.  So what we want to know is:
     what monthly payment is needed so that the balance of the
     savings account will be identical to the balance of the balloon
     loan after n payments?
 
     The formula for the principal of the balloon loan at the
     end of the nth month is:
 
          p[n] = p[0] * (1 + i)^n                          eq 5
 
     So we set this expression equal to the expression for the
     the savings account (eq 4), and we get:
 
          p[0] * (1 + i)^n  =  x * ( (1 + i)^n - 1) / i    eq 6
 
     or solving for x:
 
          x = p[0] * (1 + i)^n * i / ( (1 + i)^n - 1)      eq 7
 
 
     If (1 + i)^n is large enough (say greater than 5), here
     is an approximation for determining n from x, p, and i:
 
          n ~= -ln( ln(x/(i*p) ) ) / ln(1+i)               eq 8
 
     The above approximation is based upon the following approximation:
 
          ln(y - 1)  ~=  ln y  -  1/y
 
                                                           eq 9
 
     Which is within 2% for y >= 5.
 
     For example, a $100000 loan at 1% monthly, paying $1028.61
     per month should be paid in 360 months.  The approximation
     yields 358.9 payments.
 
     If this were your 30 year mortgage and you were paying $1028.61
     per month and you wanted to see the effect of paying $1050
     per month, the approximation tells you that it would be paid
     off in 303.5 months (25 years and 3.5 months).  If you stick
     304 months into the equation for x (eq 7), you get $1051.04, so
     it is fairly close.  This approximation does not work, though,
     for very small interest rates or for a small number of payments.
     The rule is to get a rough idea first of what (1 + i)^n is.
     If that is greater than 5, the approximation works pretty
     well.  In the examples given, (1 + i)^n is about 36.
 
 
     Finding i given n, x, and p is not as easy.  If i is less than
     5% per payment period, the following equation approximately
     holds for i:
 
          i = -(1/n) * ln(1 - i*p/x)                       eq 10
 
     There is no direct solution to this, but you can do it by
     Newton-Raphson approximation.  Begin with a guess, i[0].
     Then apply:
 
 
                       x*(1 - i[k]*p/x) * (n*i[k] + ln(1 - i[k]*p/x))
       i[k+1] = i[k] - ----------------------------------------------
                             x*n*(1 - i[k]*p/x)  -  p
 
                                                           eq 11
 
     You must start with i too big, because eq 10 has a solution
     at i=0, and that's not the one you want to end up with.
 
     Example:  Let the loan be for p=$10000, x=$50/week for
     5 years (n=260).  Let i[0] = 20% per annum or 0.3846%
     per week.  Since i must be a fraction rather than a percent,
     i[0] = 0.003846.  Then, applying eq 11:
 
       i[1] = 0.003077
 
       i[2] = 0.002479
 
       i[3] = 0.002185
 
       i[4] = 0.002118
 
       i[5] = 0.002115
 
     The series is clearly beginning to converge here.
 
     To get i[5] as an annual percentage rate, multiply by 52 weeks
     in a year and then by 100%, so i[5] = 10.997% per annum.
     Substituting i[5] back into eq 7, we get x = $50.04, so it
     works pretty well.
 
 
     The theory of interest, by Stephen G. Kellison.  Homewood, Ill., R. D.
     Irwin, 197o-.
 
 
 
24Q.- Euler's formula e^(i Pi) = - 1 ...
 
      e^(ip) = -1
 
      where i = sqrt(-1), p = pi ...
 
 
 
Copyright Notice
 
Copyright (c) 1993   A. Lopez-Ortiz
 
 
--------------------------------------------------------------------------
Questions and Answers Edited and Compiled by:
 
Alex Lopez-Ortiz                              [email protected]
Department of Computer Science                      University of Waterloo
Waterloo, Ontario                                                   Canada