T.R | Title | User | Personal Name | Date | Lines |
---|
1751.1 | set theory : naive. | WECARE::GRIFFIN | | Tue May 18 1993 01:40 | 14 |
| Aleph-null (that's Hebrew by the way, not Arabic) is the cardinal
number of the set of integers N.
Aleph (no subscript) is the cardinal number of the reals, R.
Probably what you're thinking of is a sequence of increasingly large
cardinal numbers, starting with Aleph-null, and thereafter each
cardinal number is the number of the "power set" of the preceding
cardinal, as in
aleph-null, 2 (raised to the aleph-null), 2 (raised to 2 to the
aleph-null), etc ...
John
|
1751.2 | Zermalo and Fraenkel started with nothing | VMSDEV::HALLYB | Fish have no concept of fire | Tue May 18 1993 09:16 | 13 |
| Aleph times aleph equals (the same) aleph. So you didn't one-up him.
Now if you had said "2 to the aleph ``IS NOT''", you'd have scored.
Alephs are cardinal numbers, the sideways-8 infinity is not. But your
pal was speaking in cardinal (counting) terms, so feel free to
interpret his "infinity" as Aleph-null.
There are _gobs_ of infinities, each one demonstrably larger than the
preceding. Not just by repeated power-set applications, either.
A good book on the subject, written in layman's terms, is titled
something like _Mathematics and the Infinite_, by Rudy Rucker.
John
|
1751.3 | | CSC32::D_DERAMO | Dan D'Eramo, Customer Support Center | Tue May 18 1993 11:42 | 12 |
| I have never seen "Aleph (no subscript)" used as the
cardinality of the reals R. Usually "c" is used as the
cardinality of "the continuum" (the reals).
Also, it is independent of the other axioms of set theory
whether the cardinaly of 2^(Aleph x) is Aleph x+1. The Beth
sequence is defined so that Beth-null is Aleph-null, and
Beth-n+1 is 2^Beth-n, etc.. So Beth-1 is c, but Aleph 1
is not necessarily c.
Dan
|
1751.4 | one way to measure infinity | HANNAH::OSMAN | see HANNAH::IGLOO$:[OSMAN]ERIC.VT240 | Tue May 18 1993 12:06 | 74 |
|
Here's how I like to think of it. We start with a question such as:
Are there more counting numbers or more even numbers ?
One person says
Well, the even numbers skip every other counting number, so "obviously"
although there's an infinite of each set, there are "really" twice
as many counting numbers.
But the other person says
Well, we can pairwise match up the counting numbers with the even
numbers like this:
1 2
2 4
3 6
4 8
5 10
...
Obviously, there's a match for each "all the way up", so there's the
*same* number of counting numbers as even numbers.
I believe this second argument is what math folks agree with, and hence
counting numbers and even numbers represent two infinities of the "same size".
But, now consider comparing all the decimal numbers between 0 and 1 with the
counting numbers. Which infinity is larger now ? Well, we could start
matching them like this:
1 .1
2 .2
3 .3
...
10 .10
Whoops! This wasn't a good matching, since 10 and 1 both matched .1. Let's
try to do it another way:
1 .111111...
2 .222222...
3 .333333...
...
10 .10101010....
11 .1111111.....
Oh well, that didn't work either, since 1 and 11 both matched the same value.
How about
1 .01
2 .001
3 .0001
...
Hey, that looks like it actually works ! Clearly, we've found a way to match
every counting number with a unique number between 0 and 1. But we've obviously
left out "quite a few" of the numbers between 0 and 1, since for example, no
counting number will match .2 or .33. So, there's many *more* numbers between
0 and 1 than counting numbers, and hence the "infinity" of numbers between
0 and 1 is larger than the "infinity" of counting numbers.
But something doesn't quite sit right with me about this proof yet. Just because
this *particular* matching obviously doesn't hit alot of the numbers from 0
to 1, maybe other matchings do. What right have I do judge the values of
infinities due to one simple matching I've chosen ?
Is this helpful ?
/Eric
|
1751.5 | Cantor was here | VMSDEV::HALLYB | Fish have no concept of fire | Tue May 18 1993 13:35 | 20 |
| > I believe this second argument is what math folks agree with, and hence
> counting numbers and even numbers represent two infinities of the "same size".
It's a matter of definition, not agreement. Two sets have the same
cardinality if their elements can be placed into 1-to-1 correspondence.
Period. There may be many ways -not- to place elements into a 1-to-1
correspondence, but all that is needed is ONE successful way, and they
are the "same size".
> But something doesn't quite sit right with me about this proof yet. Just because
> this *particular* matching obviously doesn't hit alot of the numbers from 0
> to 1, maybe other matchings do. What right have I do judge the values of
> infinities due to one simple matching I've chosen ?
Yep, you can't appeal to failure to make the case. What you have to do
is prove by contradiction, i.e., assume a 1-to-1 correspondence exists
and then show it does not really contain all of the elements of the
"bigger" set. Not hard to do once you know the trick...
John
|
1751.6 | | WECARE::GRIFFIN | | Tue May 18 1993 18:42 | 7 |
| re. .3
See A.G. Hamilton's "Numbers, Sets and Axioms", pp 73-78.
It may not be the common notation.
John
|
1751.7 | Different concepts of size. | CADSYS::COOPER | Topher Cooper | Wed May 19 1993 15:47 | 27 |
| For what it is worth, there are different possible mathematical
concepts around which can be loosely translated into ordinary English
as describing the "size" of an infinite set.
What we have been discussing is "cardinality".
Measure theory is a different branch of mathematics, and as I
understand it, it gives an answer closer to our ordinary understanding
when we ask "which is 'larger' the set of integers or the set of
even integers". It says that the integers is the larger set (has
larger measure) of the two -- in fact, that it is twice as large.
You can think of this as based on answering the question, "if I select
an integer at random what is the ratio of the probabilities that it
is even vs that it is an integer." The answer is, of course, 1/2.
This is actually backwards. Modern treatments of probability theory
when applied to such questions as what does it mean to "select any
integer at random" (as well as similar but even more tricky questions
dealing with reals) generally depend on measure theory to describe what
is going on.
Don't ask for details, that's pretty much the extent of my knowledge.
(Or ask if you want, I guess, but you are unlikely to get an answer
from me).
Topher
|
1751.8 | Different concepts, same answer (in this case) | VMSDEV::HALLYB | Fish have no concept of fire | Thu May 20 1993 10:19 | 7 |
| re: .7
Intuition aside, how do you get a probability of one-half?
The measure of the set of even integers is the same as the measure
of the set of all integers: zero.
John
|
1751.9 | What Cantor did | WIBBIN::NOYCE | It's the memory interface, stupid! | Thu May 20 1993 10:52 | 8 |
| Re .4 to prove that there are more reals than integers, use "Cantor
diagonalization" (alluded to in .5).
Assume you have a 1-1 mapping R(I) of the positive integers to the reals
between 0 and 1, and derive a contradiction -- namely, a real number that
isn't included in the mapping. Simply pick a number that differs from R(1)
in its first decimal digit, and differs from R(2) in its second decimal digit,
etc. Clearly it is different from any number already in the mapping.
|
1751.10 | Not my (admitedly limited) understanding. | CADSYS::COOPER | Topher Cooper | Thu May 20 1993 11:01 | 20 |
| RE: .8
As I said, I don't know anything much about measure theory. But if you
read my "think of it as if" you'll see that I'm talking about the
measure of the integers and even integers in the *integers* where their
measure is definitely not zero.
Even if we were talking about their measure in the reals, however, my
scientific-american-level knowledge of measure theory says (if it is
not way off base) that you can speak of ratios of measures which are
zero overall. This is done by means of limits, and described in terms
of relative "density". As I said, don't ask me for the details (one
of these days, I have promised myself, I'm going to get a solid
introduction to measure theory). A familiar example is that the
probability of drawing a sample from the standard normal of exactly 0
is 0, as is the probability of drawing a sample of exactly 1.0, but we
can still say that there is a sense (based on limits and exemplified by
the probability density function) in which their ratio is exp(-.5).
Topher
|
1751.11 | | HANNAH::OSMAN | see HANNAH::IGLOO$:[OSMAN]ERIC.VT240 | Thu May 20 1993 11:24 | 13 |
|
o.k. I picked an integer at random. But I don't yet know if it's even. It
seems to be quite a large integer and I'm reading it, and I haven't reached the
end yet to see if it ends in an even digit...
(just to make the point that truly "picking an integer at random" can produce
some quite large ones. We tend to forget that in our limited world of
pseudorandomness)
/Eric
|
1751.12 | | CSC32::D_DERAMO | Dan D'Eramo, Customer Support Center | Thu May 20 1993 11:52 | 5 |
| Measures can be defined on countable sets, and can even be
defined in such a way that both the even natural numbers and
the odd natural numbers have measure 1/2.
Dan
|
1751.13 | | VMSDEV::HALLYB | Fish have no concept of fire | Thu May 20 1993 12:10 | 8 |
| > Measures can be defined on countable sets, and can even be
> defined in such a way that both the even natural numbers and
> the odd natural numbers have measure 1/2.
No quarrel here. Do you think you could also define a measure so that
the evens have measure 1/3 and the odds have measure 2/3?
John
|
1751.14 | | CSC32::D_DERAMO | Dan D'Eramo, Customer Support Center | Thu May 20 1993 14:23 | 10 |
| I think that is relatively straightforward. Let m be any
measure on the natural numbers, let E and O be the evens and
odds. Just define m' to be
1 m(A intersect E) 2 m(A intersect O)
m'(A) = - ---------------- + - ----------------
3 m(E) 3 m(O)
Dan
|
1751.15 | So, nothing is special about � then | VMSDEV::HALLYB | Fish have no concept of fire | Thu May 20 1993 15:43 | 4 |
| Thanks, Dan. I knew an odd integer was more likely to come up than
an even one. :-)
John (wondering if Eric needs another RA92 to store his random integer)
|
1751.16 | | CSC32::D_DERAMO | Dan D'Eramo, Customer Support Center | Fri May 21 1993 14:18 | 8 |
| > 1 m(A intersect E) 2 m(A intersect O)
> m'(A) = - ---------------- + - ----------------
> 3 m(E) 3 m(O)
Well, not for *any* measure m, but for any measure for which
neither m(E) nor m(O) is zero. :-)
Dan
|
1751.17 | Pick a number... | TAV02::NITSAN | One side will make you larger | Mon May 24 1993 03:33 | 25 |
| re: .7,.11
Consider the following sequence:
1, 3, 2, 5, 7, 4, 9, 11, 6, 13, 15, 8, 17, 19, 10, 21, 23, 12, ...
^ ^ ^ ^ ^ ^
Picking a random element of this sequence, what's the probability of
the picked element to be odd? Isn't it 2/3? On the other hand, isn't
picking a random element of this sequence equivalent to picking a
random (positive) integer? My point is, "picking a random integer"
or, more generally, "picking a random element" of an infinite set,
is not really defined.
BTW, Alef does not realy resemble 4 (what reply was that?), it looks
like:
\ |
/\ |
| \'
| \
Is there any information about "infinities" which are "larger" (by
definition) than Alef-null, but "smaller" than Alef (or C)? Do they
exist, proved not to exist, or unknown?
-- Nitsan
|
1751.18 | Not solved | VMSDEV::HALLYB | Fish have no concept of fire | Mon May 24 1993 10:23 | 8 |
| > Is there any information about "infinities" which are "larger" (by
> definition) than Alef-null, but "smaller" than Alef (or C)? Do they
> exist, proved not to exist, or unknown?
Also known as The continuum hypothesis. I think it's an open problem.
Or possibly independent of the rest of mathematics.
John
|
1751.19 | From the natural number *sequence* ... | CADSYS::COOPER | Topher Cooper | Mon May 24 1993 15:43 | 60 |
| RE: .17 (Nitsan)
> Consider the following sequence:
> 1, 3, 2, 5, 7, 4, 9, 11, 6, 13, 15, 8, 17, 19, 10, 21, 23, 12, ...
> ^ ^ ^ ^ ^ ^
>
> Picking a random element of this sequence, what's the probability of
> the picked element to be odd? Isn't it 2/3? On the other hand, isn't
> picking a random element of this sequence equivalent to picking a
> random (positive) integer?
As I understand it, the answer is "No". Measure theory is based
on the concept of (open or closed) intervals within sets. By changing
the order you have changed the definition of what constitutes an
interval, and therefore, what the probability is. The probability
is defined on the *sequence* of natural numbers, not the set.
I'm going to attempt a hand-waving definition to give what I understand
to be the idea. In fact, there is some severe circularity here, which
is why you need a fairly sophisticated kind of mathematics (measure
theory) to put the whole thing on a firm footing.
Imagine that you select an arbitrary interval of length N. Here is
where I handwave since I am speaking of "arbitrary" mostly to avoid
saying "random". (On the integers, the concept of length is pretty
clear -- but, measure theory was first invented, I believe, to put the
concept of geometric "measures" such as length, area, and volume on a
firm, formal basis -- its, rather tricky otherwise). On any such
interval, I have a clear, unambiguous definition (frequentist) of
choosing an even integer. What that value is will depend on N and
on how I chose which interval. But if I let N grow indefinitely, I
will find that the probability of even integers among the integers
in my intervals will converge to 1/2. This is pretty much independent
of how I choose my intervals, as long as I choose them "reasonably"
("reasonable" being well-defined in the theory; in fact, for this
specific case, I don't think I need "reasonable", since I can't think
of a method of choosing which will prevent convergence).
>My point is, "picking a random integer"
> or, more generally, "picking a random element" of an infinite set,
> is not really defined.
If this were the case, then most of statistics -- which routinely
depends on taking a finite sample from infinite sets -- would be on
shaky grounds. This is precisely the problem that Kolomogorov solved
by applying measure theory to probability theory's foundations. It is
true that one random sampling of an arbitrary infinite set, especially
a non-countable set, is not well defined. But sampling an infinite set
with the right structure (divisible into intervals) *is* well defined
when a measure (specifically a measure which meets the additional
requirements of a "probability measure") can be imposed. Different
structures -- corresponding to different definitions of a "sample"
on the unstructured set -- will result in different probabilities. I
believe, however, that the results are unambiguous if you use intervals
on the integers or reals which are based on the "standard" ordering,
if you restrict yourself to probability measures, and if you require
that they "degenerate" to the finite population frequentist definition
of probability values when the populations become finite.
Topher
|
1751.20 | | CSC32::D_DERAMO | Dan D'Eramo, Customer Support Center | Mon May 24 1993 16:37 | 26 |
| >.17
> Is there any information about "infinities" which are "larger" (by
> definition) than Alef-null, but "smaller" than Alef (or C)? Do they
> exist, proved not to exist, or unknown?
>.18
> Or possibly independent of the rest of mathematics.
Cantor asked if any cardinals existed between that of the
integers and that of the reals. The statement that no such
cardinal exists is known as CH, the Continuum Hypothesis.
Godel showed that if the usual axiomitization of set theory
is consistent, then it remains consistent if you also add
AC (the Axiom of Choice) and CH (and even GCH, the Generalized
Continuum Hypothesis, which states that there is no cardinal
properly between any infinite cardinal X and the power set of
X).
Cohen showed that if the usual axiomitization of set theory
is consistent, then it remains consistent if you also add
AC and not-CH (or if you add not-AC and "the reals cannot be
well-ordered").
Dan
|
1751.21 | Kolmogorov got it right with probability 1 | VMSDEV::HALLYB | Fish have no concept of fire | Wed May 26 1993 11:34 | 33 |
| > As I understand it, the answer is "No". Measure theory is based
> on the concept of (open or closed) intervals within sets. By changing
> the order you have changed the definition of what constitutes an
> interval, and therefore, what the probability is. The probability
> is defined on the *sequence* of natural numbers, not the set.
I disagree with this and the reasoning that follows.
One of the main properties of a measure is countable additivity,
i.e., �[U Ai] = sum(�[Ai]). I.e., for pairwise disjoint Ai the
measure of their union is the sum of the individual measures. This is
for any countable collection Ai of measurable sets.
What then is the probability of choosing, say, 47 from the integers?
All along we have been implicitly assuming a uniform distribution.
�({47}) cannot be 0, since by countable additivity we would rapidly
conclude the probability of selecting any integer is 0, but we know the
probability is �(Z) = 1 by definition of a probability measure.
�({47}) cannot be less than 0 (again by definition) nor greater than 0
because then �(Z) would be infinite (by countable additivity over the
individual points), but we know �(Z) = 1.
Conclusion: single points are not measurable sets when the probability
measure is uniform over the integers.
But the entire limiting process in .19 depends on the concept of being
able to measure single points, forming a sequence of probability measures.
Which is fine for any interval of length N, but not fine "in the limit"
since the sequence of measures does not converge to a measure.
John
|
1751.22 | Don't think it works that way. | CADSYS::COOPER | Topher Cooper | Wed May 26 1993 14:58 | 67 |
| RE: .21
As I have said before, I know very little about measure theory -- I
only know a bit about what I have been told about how it has been
applied and what problems it solves.
First off, let me say that I agree completely that there is no such
sampling distribution as the discrete uniform distribution over all
integers. And I completely agree that the probability of drawing any
integer -- or any finite set of integers -- from such a distribution if
it existed would be zero (we can see this by taking the limit, for
example). I think that your reasoning is wrong here, however.
Keep in mind that probability is defined in terms of measure theory. I
have reversed the dependency for rhetorical convenience. Measure
theory is, though, more general. Though there is no (uniform)
probability distribution over the integers more general measure theory
may be applied.
Let's start with sampling from the normal distribution. Any time I
do so, I am taking a single point -- with probability 0 -- from an
infinite set. Which would *appear* to be a counter-example to your
argument but is not. The reason is that the set is non-countable so
"countable additivity" you invoked in your argument does not apply.
But wait...
Let's derive another distribution from the normal one. I'll call it
the RatNormal distribution. It is simply the normal distribution
restricted to rational values. This is a countable -- though not
discrete -- distribution. One can clearly integrate this (over the
rationals) and get a value of 1. One can clearly sample from this
distribution and get out a rational whose individual probability
is zero. And yet we are summing a countable number of zero
probabilities and getting a finite sum.
Here is a complementary example which illustrates a problem with your
argument. Is there a *continuous* uniform distribution of infinite
width? No more than for the discrete uniform distribution family.
But your argument would, since we are not dealing with countable
sums, not exclude this pseudo-distribution. Is it excluded for
completely different reasons than the discrete case? I think not --
I think that the same argument applies to both cases.
A "point" (single number) can be viewed as a limit to a sequence of
intervals as the width of that interval goes to zero. This is the
justification for the probability density function of a distribution
for example. In fact, in formal analysis, this is how real numbers
are defined (though rationals do not depend on that -- in fact, the
intervals have rational end-points/width). The problem with the
infinite uniform distributions is not that points have measure zero,
but that all *finite intervals* have measure zero. This is where
both the Normal and RatNormal distributions are different.
Countable additivity has a discontinuity when adding up zeros.
Aleph-null*0 is, in general, ill-defined. Depending on how you go
about adding them up you can get different values.
As I understand it, measure theory allows you to assign meaning, under
some circumstances to ratios of zero-measures. This makes sense when
you remember that while a/0 is undefined for a ~= 0 (since there is
no x which solves the equation a = x*0); the expression 0/0 is
"meaningless" rather than undefined (since *any* x will solve the
equation 0 = x*0). If one carefully defines what one means then
you can attach a meaning to a ratio of things with measure zero. I
think that this may require non-standard analysis, however.
Topher
|
1751.23 | Like Ar38 and Ar40, this discussion is starting to diffuse | VMSDEV::HALLYB | Fish have no concept of fire | Thu May 27 1993 09:32 | 28 |
| > discrete -- distribution. One can clearly integrate this (over the
> rationals) and get a value of 1.
Not true. The integral of any function over a set of measure 0 is 0.
> Countable additivity has a discontinuity when adding up zeros.
> Aleph-null*0 is, in general, ill-defined. Depending on how you go
> about adding them up you can get different values.
I don't follow this. Surely sum(i=0..oo)[0] = 0, which was the
principle I was using. You can play games with the summand and force
some odd-looking results (e.g., the Grandi series +1-1+1-1...) but
that's due to fiddling with the summand. If you add 0 indefinitely,
you'll get a 0 sum.
It is certainly true that there are countless :-) distributions where
one samples a value that a priori had probability 0 of being chosen.
In fact, with probability 1 one selects an element that had probability
0 of being chosen. I don't think measure theory enters into this
apparent paradox, though.
One can define a series of rational numbers that approach, say, sqrt(2)
in the limit. Yet the limiting point is not a rational number.
I think that's the sort of thing you're doing by developing a series
of measures on finite intervals and then �viola� taking the limit and
saying "see, the answer must be �".
John
|
1751.24 | Rationality. | CADSYS::COOPER | Topher Cooper | Thu May 27 1993 14:32 | 93 |
| RE: .23 (John)
>> discrete -- distribution. One can clearly integrate this (over the
>> rationals) and get a value of 1.
>
> Not true. The integral of any function over a set of measure 0 is 0.
Terminology mismatch here. You are talking about, what I would
describe as taking the integral over the reals but with irrationals
having zero probability. When I speak of doing integration over the
rationals, I'm talking about integration with the rationals as their
domain (the range is real, however). It isn't zero at irrationals
its undefined. The measure of the rationals in the
rationals is not zero. That the reals have measure 0 in the complex
numbers does not mean that integration over the complex plane means
that all integration over the reals is zero.
> I don't follow this. Surely sum(i=0..oo)[0] = 0, which was the
> principle I was using. You can play games with the summand and force
> some odd-looking results (e.g., the Grandi series +1-1+1-1...) but
> that's due to fiddling with the summand. If you add 0 indefinitely,
> you'll get a 0 sum.
The Grandi series is a good example. You can define *how* you want to
sum the Grandi series and get a reasonable -- even consistent (as long
as you don't violate your assumptions about how the addition is to be
done) -- result. But without that additional information about how
the sum is to be totalled the Grandi sequence has no limit.
If you add 0 indefinitely (an unspecified finite number of times,
however large) you *will* get 0, but if you add 0 an aleph0 number of
times you need to specify how the addition is to be done to make any
sense of it. Adding zero an aleph0 number of times is equivalent to
multiplying 0 by aleph0 which is meaningless in the same sense as 0/0
is meaningless.
Now, as I understand it, if you restrict yourself to standard analysis
and its associated calculus, then you can get away with infinitely
summing zero to zero. And in fact, that is sufficient for handling
probability theory over finite sets and over the integers. But you
need measure theory (based on non-standard analysis) to deal with the
reals.
> It is certainly true that there are countless :-) distributions where
> one samples a value that a priori had probability 0 of being chosen.
> In fact, with probability 1 one selects an element that had probability
> 0 of being chosen. I don't think measure theory enters into this
> apparent paradox, though.
It doesn't, perhaps, "enter into it", but, according to Kolomogorov it
is required to resolve it on a firm, formal basis. Your actual sample
events (reals) have zero probability. Overall you need the total
probability to sum to one. To do so you use measure theory to define
your proability measure in terms of intervals and your final outcomes
in terms of limits of those intervals. That justifies the probability
density function which allows us to integrate to the cumulative
probability function (at least for continuous CPFs). The PDF makes
meaningful such statements as "the probability of 0 relative to 1 from
the normal distribution is exp(-�)".
> One can define a series of rational numbers that approach, say, sqrt(2)
> in the limit. Yet the limiting point is not a rational number.
> I think that's the sort of thing you're doing by developing a series
> of measures on finite intervals and then �viola� taking the limit and
> saying "see, the answer must be �".
Guilty as charged. I didn't prove anything. I illustrated the process
by which the concept of the density of infinite (countable) sets in
other infinite (ordered countable) sets is defined. I have been told
that this definition can be formalized and proven consistent using
measure theory. Any finite interval of length at least two will have
associated with it a real number representing the ratio of even
integers to total integers (i.e., the intervals size) in that interval.
If you allow those intervals to expand in size you will get a perfectly
classical series to sum. If you reqire "intervals" to be based on
locality based on the standard ordering of the integers, those series
will consistently converge and will consistently converge to the same
value (although the specific series will depend on how you select the
position of the interval of each size).
We are dealing with perfectly classical series convergence -- not
improperly extrapolating a property (membership in the rationals) to
their infinite sum. The rationals are not closed under addition. The
limit of a series of quite proper probability distributions is
not necessarily a proper probability distribution; e.g., the uniform
distribution of infinite width, or the delta distribution (which among
other definitions is the limit of uniform distributions as the width
goes to 0). Sometimes such improper distributions are handy though,
if you are careful with them, and clean up the mess afterwards. Non-
standard analysis was in large part motivated by the delta function/
distribution.
Topher
|
1751.25 | why doesn't this work for integers too | HANNAH::OSMAN | see HANNAH::IGLOO$:[OSMAN]ERIC.VT240 | Thu May 27 1993 17:29 | 32 |
| >Re .4 to prove that there are more reals than integers, use "Cantor
>diagonalization" (alluded to in .5).
>
>Assume you have a 1-1 mapping R(I) of the positive integers to the reals
>between 0 and 1, and derive a contradiction -- namely, a real number that
>isn't included in the mapping. Simply pick a number that differs from R(1)
>in its first decimal digit, and differs from R(2) in its second decimal digit,
>etc. Clearly it is different from any number already in the mapping.
My first reaction, of course, was that this was kind of clever.
But now I'm a bit troubled again. Going back to the mapping from counting
numbers to even numbers again:
e(1) 0
e(2) 2
e(3) 4
e(4) 6
e(5) 8
...
We ask the same question now, namely "have we hit all the even numbers" ?
Well, why can't we do the diagonal thing here too. Namely, construct an
even number that differs from e(1) in first digit, and differs from e(2)
in second digit, and differs from e(3) in third digit etc. Clearly, this
new even number is not in our list, and hence we haven't provided a complete
mapping.
/Eric
|
1751.26 | Trickier than it appears -- but it does work. | CADSYS::COOPER | Topher Cooper | Thu May 27 1993 18:02 | 18 |
| RE: .25 (Eric)
You have constructed an "integer" with an infinite number of digits.
There is no such beast -- all integers have a finite number of
digits. As a consequence, the number you have constructed which is
not on the list, doesn't belong on the list.
Although essentially correct the process of diagonalizing the reals is
actually a little trickier than the description given. You have to be
careful because what you are constructing in the diagonalization is a
real *representation* that isn't on the list of representations. Since
many reals (specifically those rationals whose reduced numerator will
divide into a power of the representation radix) have more than one
representation you may discover an value which is on the list, just
represented in another way. You have to set the whole thing up
carefully to avoid this problem.
Topher
|
1751.27 | | CSC32::D_DERAMO | Dan D'Eramo, Customer Support Center | Thu May 27 1993 21:41 | 70 |
| I recall reading that Cantor's argument that the reals are not
countable did not use decimal or binary representation.
Here is one proof which uses only order properties of the reals.
If a(0), a(1), a(2), ..., a(n), ... is a countable sequence of
reals, then define b(0), c(0), b(1), c(1), b(2), c(2), ... such
that
b(0) < b(1) < b(2) < ... < c(2) < c(1) < c(0)
Simply take b(0) to be a(0), and "cross out" all a(n) <= b(0).
If the entire sequence of a's was just crossed out, then
obviously the sequence of a's didn't contain any reals greater
than b(0), and so could not be a list of all of the reals.
Otherwise, some a's remain, and the first one remaining in the
sequence is taken as c(0), and all a's still remaining which
are >= c(0) are now crossed out.
Repeat this process for k = 1, 2, 3, ... If no a's remain,
then the original sequence of a's did not include any reals
between b(k-1) and c(k-1). If a's remain, select the first
in the sequence as b(k), and cross out all a's <= b(k). If
all the a's are gone, then the reals between b(k) and c(k-1)
were missing from the original enumeration. Otherwise, take
c(k) as the first a in the sequence still remaining.
The above process may stop because the sequence of a's did
not include any reals between the largest (most recently
chosen) b and the smallest (also most recently chosen) c.
Or it may continue "forever" and allow us to define the
b and c sequences such that
b(0) < b(1) < b(2) < ... < c(2) < c(1) < c(0)
Let B be the least upper bound of the b's, and let C be the
greatest lower bound of the c's; we have
b(0) < b(1) < b(2) < ... < B <= C < ... < c(2) < c(1) < c(0)
Any x such that B <= x <= C cannot have been among the a(n) -- if
it did, it would have eventually been chosen as one of the b's or c's.
So either way, the list of a's does not enumerate all the reals.
I think Cantor's original diagonal argument applied to a set A
and its power set P(A) = { B | B is a subset of A }
Given any f : A -> P(A), then the "diagonal set"
D = { x in A | x is not in f(x) } is a subset of A
which is not in the range of f.
This shows that no set A can be mapped onto all of P(A),
and gives an explicit subset D of A which is not "touched"
by f. If A is the positive integers, you can picture this
as
x 0 in f(x)? 1 in f(x)? 2 in f(x)? ...
-----------------------------------------------------------
0 yes no yes
1 no no yes
2 no yes yes
.
.
.
Then run down the diagonal inverting the yes/no's to see what
is in the diagonal set D.
Dan
|
1751.28 | Interesting proof, Dan. | CADSYS::COOPER | Topher Cooper | Fri May 28 1993 12:14 | 20 |
| RE: .27 (Dan)
> I recall reading that Cantor's argument that the reals are not
> countable did not use decimal or binary representation.
Could be, but the diagonalization proof using decimal representation is
usually presented as Cantor's proof.
> I think Cantor's original diagonal argument applied to a set A
> and its power set P(A) = { B | B is a subset of A }
In case anyone has lost track -- this is not intended as an alternate
way of showing that the reals are not countable (i.e., equal in "size"
to the integers). One can consistently assume either that the size
of the power set of the integers (aleph-sub-one) is equal to the
size of the set of reals (a.k.a., the size of the continuum, or C) --
which is refered to as the continuum hypothesis, or that they are
not equal.
Topher
|
1751.29 | Have we discovered a new concept? | VMSDEV::HALLYB | Fish have no concept of fire | Fri May 28 1993 13:59 | 18 |
| .24> The measure of the rationals in the rationals is not zero.
Tell me more. What IS "the measure of the rationals in the rationals",
and how is it calculated? What sets of rationals are measurable? Bearing
in mind that measure must be translation invariant and countably additive.
.24> That the reals have measure 0 in the complex
> numbers does not mean that integration over the complex plane means
> that all integration over the reals is zero.
The integral over a set of measure zero is always 0. Now that's a fact.
(Well, at least if the function is integrable over the set).
Speaking colloquially: the rationals have "length" 0, so any integral
(i.e., any area) with one side 0 will necessarily be 0. Likewise the
reals have "area" 0 so any volume based on area 0 will also be volume 0.
John
|
1751.30 | Just define things carefully. | CADSYS::COOPER | Topher Cooper | Fri May 28 1993 16:21 | 39 |
| RE: .29 (John)
Well, I keep saying that I'm out of my depth on this, and perhaps I
completely misunderstood what was explained to me, but you haven't
convinced me of that yet.
> Tell me more. What IS "the measure of the rationals in the rationals",
> and how is it calculated? What sets of rationals are measurable? Bearing
> in mind that measure must be translation invariant and countably additive.
If it is a probability measure then the measure of the rationals in the
rationals is one. In other words if you are selecting a single
rational from the rationals -- however you do it -- the probability
that you will end up with some rational will be 1.
You cannot, of course, do a Reimann (sp?) integral over the rationals
since it is only defined over R^d, but you can do a Lebesgue integral
to get the "area" under the rationals in such a way as to completely
ignore the reals.
Because of additivity you cannot assign a zero measure to individual
rationals and end up with a total measure of the whole set with
anything other than zero. But you can refuse to assign a meaning to
the measure of an individual point and instead talk about measures of
finite, positive-lengthed rational intervals and (countable) unions of
those intervals. The limit of the measure of a sequence of such
intervals goes to zero as the length of the interval goes to zero, but
that doesn't mean that the measure on the point itself is zero. We
can talk about the measure of infinite (obviously countable) sets of
rationals.
Imagine we sample the rationals with the following restriction: the
probability that the value is less than a rational value R is the same
as the probability that a value sampled from the normal distribution.
That's my RatNormal distribution. Do you really claim that no such
distribution can exist? I would say that if the foundations of
probability theory are insufficient to handle this than they need work.
Topher
|
1751.31 | Retraction. | CADSYS::COOPER | Topher Cooper | Fri May 28 1993 17:05 | 26 |
| RE: .28 (Me)
> One can consistently assume either that the size of the power set of
> the integers (aleph-sub-one) is equal to the size of the set of reals
> (a.k.a., the size of the continuum, or C) -- which is refered to as the
> continuum hypothesis, or that they are not equal.
Dan has sent me mail informing me that this is not true -- that C is
equal to the size of the power set of the integers. After massaging my
aging memory for a while, I realize that he is quite correct, and that
I confused two theorems of Cantor (I believe that he failed to prove
either one of them). The first, which remained unsolved for a long
time, was the continuum hypothesis -- that there exists no cardinality
(size) between the cardinality of N (natural numbers) and the
cardinality of P(N) (power set of N). Gauss showed that you could
consistently assume either the continuum hypothesis or its converse.
(This was later extended to the generalized continuum hypothesis which
is about infinite cardinalities between any infinite set and its
power-set). The other hypothesis -- related to the continuum
hypothesis by Cantor -- was the hypothesis that C (the number of reals)
was strictly less than the size of P(N). This was, however, shown to
be false -- that the cardinality of P(N) is equal to C.
Sorry for confusing things with my faulty memory.
Topher
|
1751.32 | | CSC32::D_DERAMO | Dan D'Eramo, Customer Support Center | Wed Jun 02 1993 14:38 | 27 |
| Cantor certainly knew and showed that the cardinality of the
reals ("c") was the same as the cardinality of the power set
of the naturals ("two to the aleph-null"). As he looked at
the cardinalities of various subsets of the reals, he found
they came in three types, finite, infinite and countable, and
infinite of cardinality c.
For example, every nonempty perfect subset of the reals has
cardinality c (examples are the well-known Cantor set, or any
interval [a,b] with a < b). Every open subset includes an
interval [a,b] and so has cardinality c. Every closed subset
can be written as a disjoint union of a possibly empty perfect
set and a set which is finite or countably infinite (this actually
uses a little bit of the axiom of choice).
So Cantor formulated the question CH, which stands for the
"no" answer to the question of whether there are any infinite
sets with cardinality strictly between aleph-null and c. I've
been told that Cantor was good enough that he never actually
mistakenly thought he had proved or disproved CH. Godel first
showed that if the other usually accepted axioms of set theory
were consistent, then CH (and GCH) plus those axioms are
consistent as well. Cohen showed that with the same assumption,
not-CH plus those axioms are also consistent. So CH turns out to
be independent of the other axioms of set theory.
Dan
|
1751.33 | Need to define things carefully | VMSDEV::HALLYB | Fish have no concept of fire | Mon Jun 07 1993 10:23 | 19 |
| .30>> Tell me more. What IS "the measure of the rationals in the rationals",
.30>> and how is it calculated? What sets of rationals are measurable? Bearing
.30>> in mind that measure must be translation invariant and countably additive.
>
> If it is a probability measure then the measure of the rationals in the
> rationals is one. In other words if you are selecting a single
> rational from the rationals -- however you do it -- the probability
The objection in .29 was that you (Topher) defined a function and then
used various results from probability/measure theory to justify certain
results. The problem I had with that is that you failed to demonstrate
that your RatNorm actually qualifies as a probability measure. You
need to demonstrate that it satisfies a certain number of axioms, or
properties if you dislike that use of the word "axiom", in order to
qualify as a probability measure.
Perhaps it is time to take this discussion offline.
John
|