T.R | Title | User | Personal Name | Date | Lines |
---|
1456.1 | Tarksi sphere proof | EAGLE1::BEST | R D Best, sys arch, I/O | Fri Jun 14 1991 17:23 | 8 |
| The one that I have trouble with is the claim that (and I hope I get it
right):
Tarski proved that a single sphere could be sectioned into pieces in such a
way that two spheres identical to the original could be formed.
I'll post the source when I find it. I don't have the proof, but would be
intrigued to see one.
|
1456.2 | this is impossible ! | SMAUG::ABBASI | | Fri Jun 14 1991 17:44 | 16 |
| ref .-1
you must mean a solid sphere, and when you say idetical, you mean
two new spheres, but the two new spheres not all solid (will be
partially hollow inside) , but they have same surface area as original,
that would be possible offcourse, but no way one could make 2 spheres
both solid from one solid, and both still have same surface area as
original !
my intuituition would not accept that, never mind the law of
conversation of mass !
/naser
|
1456.3 | At least in mathematics, its possible. | CADSYS::COOPER | Topher Cooper | Fri Jun 14 1991 19:14 | 35 |
| RE: .2 (/naser)
No, this is not impossible -- just not practical in the real world.
Yes, the initial "sphere" is a solid one (its actually about the union
of a sphere and its interior, rather than a sphere), but no the final
spheres "really" are identical -- they do not have any hollow places
inside. The key is that the pieces that you remove and reassemble are
not "ordinary" -- they are disconnected fractals. The proof of this
requires the Axiom of Choice which, though intuitively obvious (in
non-technical language, it just says that if you "have" a set you can
always "choose" or reference one of its elements), and consistent with
other set theoretic axioms, leads to many counterintutive results so
some mathematians feel that it "aught" not to be used. For this
reason, theorems which depend on it for their proof are usually labeled
that way.
It simply turns out that, in three dimensional space, you can cut up
any shape into some number of pieces (generally very large) -- many
consisting of fractal dust as I understand it -- and then move those
pieces around and rotate them (with each disconnected part of a piece
holding its relation to the other parts of the piece throughout the
movement/rotation) and slide them together again so that the gaps
in one fill up the gaps in the others. The result is that (there may
be some restrictions) any solid can be turned into any other solid
or set of solids, regardless of volume.
What about mass conservation? That concerns discrete matter, not
infinitely divisible points. The number of *points* in two spheres
of equal volume is the same as the number of points in one of those
two spheres so there is no extra points appearing out of nowhere.
There was a good "popular" article about this recently. I'll try
to find it.
Topher
|
1456.4 | oops, notes collision ... or did Tarski split one reply? | GUESS::DERAMO | duly noted | Fri Jun 14 1991 19:18 | 11 |
| The theorem as I remember it is that you can take a solid
sphere (treated as the set of points (x,y,z) in R^3
satisfying x^2 + y^2 + z^2 <= 1), partition it into a
finite number of sets, and move those (translations,
rotations) sets so that they recombine into two solid
spheres of the same radius as the original.
Some of the pieces can best be described as "sets of
points."
Dan
|
1456.5 | Here's the reference | EAGLE1::BEST | R D Best, sys arch, I/O | Mon Jun 17 1991 01:58 | 30 |
| The following is (of course) not a proof, but a claim that there is a proof:
{ Extracted w.o. permission from 'Tomorrow's Math' by C. Stanley Ogilvie,
c. 1962, Oxford University Press }
p. 7
' .. Other difficulties arise in connection with the volume of solids.
Intuitively, it would seem that if you start with a given finite solid object,
cut it up into a finite number of pieces, and then reassemble the same pieces in
any way, provided there are no spaces anywhere between the reassembled pieces
the new solid should have the same volume as the original.
In 1924 Banach and Tarski showed that this is not necessarily so by proving
the following extraordinary theorem: it is possible to cut a solid sphere into
a finite number of pieces and reassemble them by rigid motions (no distortion)
to form two solid spheres (no holes), each of the same size as the original one.
It might be supposed that the number of pieces in the dissection would have to
be very large. But Raphael Robinson has shown that there need be no more than
5 pieces ! These unbelievable results show that we must revise our fundamental
notion of volume. There cannot be any general definition which will preserve
volume under rigid motion -- something always previously accepted as "obvious"
..'
Here are the pointers:
'7. The Banach-Tarksi theorem was published in Fundamenta Mathematicae, Vol. 6
(1924), p. 244.
7. Raphael Robinson, Fundamenta Mathematicae, Vol. 34(1947), p. 246.
See also Amer. Math. Monthly, Vol. 55(1948), p. 459.'
|
1456.6 | If this is true, CNN would'v announced it :-) | SMAUG::ABBASI | | Mon Jun 17 1991 04:05 | 18 |
| I could never ever believe this even if i see a proof for it ,
(assuming i understood the proof :-)
this sounds like proving the grand unified field theory, except
we have to accept we live in 10 dimensional space-time continuum.
i've been struggling with a homework in Riemann surfaces, where you
connect two or more sheets along the z-values (cut branch) where the
branches of the original multi-valued complex function becomes discontinuous,
so as to construct one continuous function by jumping from sheet (domain)
to another when you hit the cut branch, however these Riemann surfaces
cannot be constructed physically since the surfaces cross over along the cut,
and the author says , only mathematically this is possible, physically you
cant do it, this sphere deal sounds something like Riemann surfaces,
out of this world :-)
/naser
|
1456.7 | | JARETH::EDP | Always mount a scratch monkey. | Mon Jun 17 1991 10:01 | 4 |
| See also topic 325.
-- edp
|
1456.8 | Recent popular article. | CADSYS::COOPER | Topher Cooper | Mon Jun 17 1991 12:21 | 26 |
| RE: .3 (me)
The article is:
Stewart, Ian; "The Ultimate Jigsaw Puzzle" _New Scientist_, Vol 130,
#1764 (13 April, 1991) pp 30-33.
This is the same Ian Stewart who has been writing Mathematical Games
for Sci. Am. of late.
The article isn't "really" about the Banach-Tarski paradox/theorem but
about a related 2D problem referred to in the article as "Tarski's
circle-squaring" problem. This asks whether a circle (including its
interior) can be divided into a finite number of pieces which can be
rigidly moved around and be assembled into a square of equal area (or,
of course, vice versa). Most of the article, however, is devoted to
providing background -- which is mostly the Banach_Tarski theorem and
its resulting paradox. (The answer, by the way, is that it has
recently been found that the answer is that you *can* disect the circle
into a square -- and you can simply rearrange the pieces without
rotations to accomplish it. It does require about 10^50 pieces to
do the trick, however. The result is general, any two shapes whose
boundaries consist of smoothly curved pieces can be disected into each
other.)
Topher
|
1456.9 | what about Pi ? | SMAUG::ABBASI | | Wed Jun 19 1991 00:01 | 4 |
| Re: .8 (Topher)
I guess I must see the article to see how they go around that
fact that squaring the circle contradicts the fact the Pi is
irrational.
|
1456.10 | | GUESS::DERAMO | duly noted | Wed Jun 19 1991 01:12 | 9 |
| >> that squaring the circle contradicts the fact that Pi is irrational.
That Pi isn't reached from the rationals by successive
quadratic extensions doesn't contradict the result. It
just means that the pieces can't be cut out of the circle
with standard "Euclidean" compass, straightedge, and
scissors.
Dan
|
1456.11 | intution on series summations | SMAUG::ABBASI | | Sun Jun 23 1991 04:06 | 5 |
| this little one might belong in here too:
the series {1/n} as n->oo , diverges.
i think most students who see this first time, and without any analysis
done, would say it converges, not diverges.
|
1456.12 | waiting for the bus | ELIS::GARSON | V+F = E+2 | Tue Jul 02 1991 07:22 | 7 |
| Here's one that I found surprising when I first encountered it.
If buses arrive at a bus stop such that the average time between
arrivals is, say, 10 minutes then the expected time you'll have to wait
for a bus is not necessarily 5 minutes. In fact it can be made arbitrarily
large. I guess I have a certain empathy with this result because I catch
the bus to work each day.
|
1456.13 | why 5 minutes expected, and not 10 minutes? | SMAUG::ABBASI | | Wed Jul 03 1991 14:45 | 3 |
| If average time between arrivals is X, should not the expected time
to wait for a bus be X too?
(pepole dont use buses much in the states, so i could be wrong :-)
|
1456.14 | | WONDER::COYLE | | Wed Jul 03 1991 15:26 | 15 |
| RE .13
The intuitive 5 minutes is because one assumes average means the
busses come at uniform 10 minute intervals. If this were the case
the five minutes makes sense because you would have a long wait of
ten minutes and a short wait of zero averageing out at five.
What I assumed the author was getting at was that the ten minute
average time does not disclose information about the distribution
of bus arivals. If in every hour you get six busses, at the hour
and the next five one minute intervals you average a bus every
ten minutes but might have to wait as long a 55 minutes.
-Joe
|
1456.15 | On the buses | ELIS::GARSON | V+F = E+2 | Fri Jul 05 1991 08:03 | 35 |
| re .13,.14
Once you realise that the expected waiting time might depend on more
than just the mean of the inter-arrival time distribution, it still isn't
intuitively obvious what the effect of differing distributions will be.
The way it was explained to me was that you are more likely to arrive
during a long gap between buses and thus have to wait a long time (while
several buses close together are pointless because if you miss one you'll
miss several). Thus any departure from a rigid cycle of a bus every 10
minutes increases the expected waiting time.
To pick up the example of .14, if k buses arrive every 10k minutes in a
fixed cycle of buses one every minute from the start of the 'cycle'
until the k buses have arrived and then nothing more for the rest of
the cycle, then assuming I got my calculation right the expected
waiting time is (81k+19)/20. Setting k=1 gives the intuitive answer of
5 minutes for that case. For the actual example of .14, k=6 gives an
expected waiting time of 25.25 minutes.
Fixed cycles of buses are all very well but any smart passenger will
find out the cycle and then can at least wait at home.
Suppose the inter-arrival time is a continuous random variable with
probability density function (pdf) p(x) = k.exp(-kx) then it can easily
be shown that the average time between buses is 1/k. This distribution
has the interesting property of being memoriless i.e. roughly speaking,
no matter how long since the last bus the average time still remaining
before the next bus is the same (I know the feeling).
Consequently the expected waiting time is 1/k i.e. twice what intuition
would suggest (and it's as if you always just missed one).
(I hope I got the details right. It's been a long time. I stand ready
to be corrected.)
|
1456.16 | nmwtp = random arrivals | AGOUTL::BELDIN | Pull us together, not apart | Fri Jul 05 1991 11:22 | 8 |
| That's as good an explanation as I ever got. :-)
Of course, the NMWTP (no memory waiting time process) is just one of
the many alternatives you might assume. Only in that case does the
logic hold true. On the other hand, did you ever hear of a bus with a
memory? :-)
Dick
|
1456.17 | More on the buses | ELIS::GARSON | V+F = E+2 | Tue Jul 09 1991 07:21 | 27 |
| re .-1
> Of course, the NMWTP (no memory waiting time process) is just one of
> the many alternatives you might assume.
Certainly.
As an alternative, suppose that the inter-arrival time is uniformly
distributed on [0,20] (so the mean is still 10), then it can be shown
that the expected time you'll have to wait for the bus is 10 * 2/3
i.e. somewhere between the 'intuitive' answer of 5 and the 'memoriless'
answer of 10.
> Only in that case does the logic hold true.
Yes. The given pdf is a special case... a case of at least theoretical
interest (but rather inappropriate for this problem).
Note that even though I just asserted that the given pdf was
'memoriless' and hand-waved that this meant that mean waiting time =
mean inter-arrival time, the mean waiting time can be found directly
from the pdf (if you like integration by parts for this particular pdf).
> On the other hand, did you ever hear of a bus with a memory? :-)
The buses may not have memory but they are controlled and scheduled by
an organisation that does.
|
1456.18 | non-mathematical aside | AGOUTL::BELDIN | Pull us together, not apart | Tue Jul 09 1991 11:56 | 14 |
| re 1456.17 by ELIS::GARSON
>The buses may not have memory but they are controlled and scheduled by
>an organisation that does.
<acid rain on>
Sorry, my parochial experience is limited to bus authorities run by
political hacks who wouldn't know a schedule if it bit them. :-(
<acid rain off>
Dick
|
1456.19 | Moved by Moderator | JARETH::EDP | Always mount a scratch monkey. | Fri Jul 26 1991 08:21 | 19 |
| ================================================================================
Note 1472.0 Also true for elevators 2 replies
HGOVC::JOELBERMAN 15 lines 21-JUL-1991 02:44
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
I think elevators (lifts) exhibit the same symptoms. Most modern
elevator controls have scheduling algorithms that try to keep them on
the ground floor when people are coming to work in the morning and
after lunch, and then keep them spaced vertically during the lunch hour and
quitting time.
I go to many taller buildings and have noticed an enormous difference
in waiting times. SOme of this may be explained by different speed
elevators, but I suspect that some companies did not apply any
mathematice to the scheduling algorithms.
Is there a general solution to the minimum latency elevator ( or bus)
problem?
/joel
|
1456.20 | Moved by Moderator | JARETH::EDP | Always mount a scratch monkey. | Fri Jul 26 1991 08:21 | 10 |
| ================================================================================
Note 1472.1 Also true for elevators 1 of 2
CIVAGE::LYNN "Lynn Yarbrough @WNP DTN 427-5663" 5 lines 25-JUL-1991 14:27
-< Eh? >-
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
I think the elevator problem is discussed in Knuth TAOCP Vol I.
I also think I detect a *reply* disguised as a *write*. If the moderator
could straighten this out (and delete this note) we might get back on
track. Or am I missing something?
|
1456.21 | intution in convergence | STAR::ABBASI | | Thu Nov 28 1991 02:06 | 27 |
| this might be trivial to some of you, but i read something that
if the ratio of the nth term of two sequences is +1 as n increases with no
limit, and one of the sequences if convergent, the other could still be
divergent !
seemed counter intuitive to me , but they give example : (hit CR)
(-1)^n
-------- other sequence (-1)^n
SQRT(n) ------- ( 1+ (-1)^n )
SQRT(n) ------
SQRT(n)
the first in convergent, the other is divergent, yet ratio of their
n terms is +1 as n->oo .
this is interesting since it is counter intutive at first, right?
i think in convergence problems one cant talk anything for granted !
/nasser
p.s reference is "George Conter, his mathematical and philosphy of the
infinite" by joseph Dauben, princeton univ. press, 1979
|
1456.22 | intution tells me this is wrong result, why? | STAR::ABBASI | | Thu Nov 28 1991 02:23 | 24 |
|
my cranky intution told me that the fourier series aproximation to
COS(t) should come out to be COS(t) (i.e. one term), but i keep getting
the a(k) coeff. zero, and the b(k) coeff. zero, so the Fourier
series is 0. (no terms)
f(t)= a0/2 + sum(1..oo)( a(k)cos(kt) + b(k)sin(kt) )
a0= 1/Pi Intgral(-Pi..Pi) of cos(t) = 0
a(k)= 1/Pi Integral(-Pi..Pi) of ( cos(t) cos(kt) ) = 0
b(k)= 1/Pi Integral(-Pi..Pi) of ( cos(t) sin(kt) ) = 0
so f(t) = 0
i either done something wrong in calcualtions even though i double
checked few times, or completely confused ,or both (most likely).
any one see where i went wrong?
thanks,
/nasser
p.s. i must reinstall MAPLE on my workstation again sometime !
|
1456.23 | a(1) isn't zero! | HERON::BLOMBERG | Trapped inside the universe | Thu Nov 28 1991 04:21 | 1 |
|
|
1456.24 | | ELIS::GARSON | V+F = E+2 | Thu Nov 28 1991 06:36 | 69 |
| re .21
>if the ratio of the nth term of two sequences is +1 as n increases with no
>limit, and one of the sequences if convergent, the other could still be
>divergent !
You mean *series* not sequences.
If lim a exists, call it a, and lim b / a exists and equals 1
n->oo n n->oo n n
Then lim b exists and equals a
n->oo n
as is reasonably intuitive.
If lim b / a exists and equals 1 and the series a converges, say to s, then
n->oo n n
you are correct in observing that the series b need not converge (and if it
does converge the limit need not be s).
>seemed counter intuitive to me
I wouldn't trust my intuition. Try some algebra...
n n n
sigma b = sigma a � (b / a ) = sigma a � (1 + b / a - 1)
i=1 i i=1 i i i i=1 i i i
n n
= sigma a + sigma a � (b / a - 1)
i=1 i i=1 i i i
Now by assumption the series a converges, say to s, and it is a well known
result that therefore the sequence a converges to 0. Also by assumption the
sequence b / a converges to 1.
n n
Thus a � (b / a - 1) converges to 0 since both factors do. This does not
n n n
however mean that the series converges, the most well-known example be 1/n.
[a sequence converging to 0 is a necessary but not sufficient condition for
the series converging]
If this series converges to a non-zero value then the series b will actually
converge but to a value other than s.
>, but they give example : (hit CR)
>
> (-1)^n
> -------- other sequence (-1)^n
> SQRT(n) ------- ( 1+ (-1)^n )
> SQRT(n) ------
> SQRT(n)
And surprise surprise evaluating a � (b / a - 1) for these sequences gives
n n n
1/n.
> i think in convergence problems one cant take anything for granted !
Agreed.
If you can't prove it rigorously then it might not be correct (which of course
applies to all mathematics).
|
1456.25 | ref .23 fouries series answer | STAR::ABBASI | | Thu Nov 28 1991 11:04 | 16 |
| ref .23
thanks, your right and my faith in fourier series has been restored.
the dumb mistake i did was during evaluating a(k) one gets this
expression
a(K)= 1/(1-k) ( sin(1-k)Pi + sin(1-k)Pi ) + ..same but with (1+k)..
so my brain lied to me and said :for all k=0..oo the sin(1-k) are zero!
so a(k) is zero for all k, offcourse i did not notice that k=1 is
speical case because of 0/0 term, and k=1 must be evaluated separtly.
and i fell in this before, gee wiz, i'll tie something on my finger from
now on to remind me about this one.
well, this goes to show that even great mathematicians make mistakes :-)
/nasser
|
1456.26 | intution on convergence | STAR::ABBASI | | Thu Nov 28 1991 11:05 | 13 |
|
ref .24, thanks, i'll go over what you wrote.
i'll blupper again something from my cranky intution without
tinking too much about it: if the *sequence* is convergent then the
the partial sum *series* must also be convergent. this got to be
correct, but i'll take your advice and try to prove rigo'rsly first.
i just like to solve problems intutivly first, then see if it is
correct, this way may be i dont have to do the thing i fear most in my
life: proofs !
/nasser
|
1456.27 | intuition works on many levels | CORREO::BELDIN_R | Pull us together, not apart | Tue Dec 03 1991 09:33 | 17 |
| <<< Note 1456.26 by STAR::ABBASI >>>
-< intution on convergence >-
...
> i just like to solve problems intutivly first, then see if it is
> correct, this way may be i dont have to do the thing i fear most in my
> life: proofs !
...
My approach is different. When my intuition at one level is weak, I use
calculation or proof to change to a different level of abstraction where my
intuition is stronger. I _never_ trust my intuition where infinities or
existence proofs are concerned.
Dick
|
1456.28 | if we know how they think, maybe i'll be better? | STAR::ABBASI | | Tue Dec 03 1991 10:19 | 12 |
| this is interesting are, to see how math people think about problems,
i got this book that talks about this, some famouse maths people are
investigated and asked questions to analyse their process of thinking.
i'll put the reference here later, it is a good reading material.
but i think, one must have an intution on what the solution looks like,
befor doing the calculations, right?.
maybe be this is too general topic to discuess with any concrete ideas.
(my intution tells me so :-)
/nasser
|
1456.29 | ref. on book | STAR::ABBASI | | Tue Dec 03 1991 23:22 | 27 |
| this is a nice little book that touches on intuition in math among
other things:
"the psychology of invention in the mathematical field" By Jacques
Hadamard. Dover edition.1954. (QA 9 H25)
contents: General views and inquiries
discussions on unconsiousness "they talk about how
the unconsiouse mind could be working on the problem without you
reliazing it"
the unconscious and discovery
the preparation stage. logic and chance
the later concious work.
discovery as a synthesis. the help signs
Different Kinds of mathematical minds
paradoxical cases of intuition
general direction of research
the general theme of the book is "how creativity is tapped in science.
the unconscious mind and discovery. intuition vs. Verbal resoning.
POINCARE's forgetting hypothesis. creative techniques of EINSTEIN,
PASCAL, WIENER and others"
i figured, when i finish reading this book, may i'll finally figure the
trick to how be good at math... nothing else seems to help...
/nasser
|
1456.30 | getting (or feeling) better at math | PULPO::BELDIN_R | Pull us together, not apart | Wed Dec 04 1991 08:12 | 21 |
| re .29
I enjoyed that book myself many years ago. To improve your math
performance, I would recommend Polya's "How to Solve It". Sorry, I don't
have any publisher information. I've found that the first hurdle to solving
math problems is just as Polya describes it, "having the problem".
What he means is that you must feel that you "own" the problem. You are
responsible, not to someone else, but to yourself for the solution. In a
sense, you have to become obsessed with the problem. And yet, you must
approach it without thinking of the consequences of success or failure.
So Polya's prescription (and mine, for what its worth) is
1) Own the problem like your life depended on it.
2) Remember its a game, not life or death.
I know it's paradoxical, but it works.
Dick
|
1456.31 | 1=0 | STAR::ABBASI | i^(-i) = SQRT(exp(PI)) | Wed Jul 15 1992 20:43 | 16 |
|
/
I= ) 1/x dx
/
integration by parts, let u=1/x , dv=dx
then du= -1/x^2 dx, v=x
/ /
then I = uv- ) v du = 1 - ) x(-1/x^2) dx= 1+ I
/ /
so I= 1+I => 1=0
/Nasser
|
1456.32 | 2=1 | STAR::ABBASI | i^(-i) = SQRT(exp(PI)) | Wed Jul 15 1992 20:55 | 29 |
| 2
/
I= ) 1/x dx
/
0
let t= x/2, then x=2t, dx=2dt =>
2 1 1 1
/ / / /
I= ) 1/x dx = ) 2 dt/2t = ) dt/t = ) dx/x (since dt=dx/2 & t=x/2)
/ / / /
0 0 0 0
2 1
/ /
so ) dx/x - ) dx/x = 0
/ /
0 0
2 2
/ |
this means ) dx/x = 0 i.e ln x | = 0 , i.e. ln 2 =0,
/ |
1 1
i.e. e^0=2, i.e. 1=2
/nasser
|
1456.33 | intution on integration | VMSINT::ABBASI | | Mon Jul 20 1992 12:09 | 8 |
| if a function is bounded => it is integrable (Riemman)
true or false?
if false, can you give an example of a bounded function that is
not integrable?
/Nasser
|
1456.34 | | HERON::BLOMBERG | Trapped inside the universe | Mon Jul 20 1992 12:23 | 7 |
|
No,
let f(x)=0 if x ix irrational, 1 if x is rational. Bounded, but
not integrable.
/�ke
|
1456.35 | | HERON::BLOMBERG | Trapped inside the universe | Mon Jul 20 1992 12:24 | 2 |
| Eh, I mean not Riemann integrable. Lebesgue integrable, yes.
|
1456.36 | any more examples? | STAR::ABBASI | i^(-i) = SQRT(exp(PI)) | Mon Jul 20 1992 12:28 | 4 |
| yes, that is the one example i knew off too, any one knows of other
examples?
thanks,
/nasser
|
1456.37 | | GUESS::DERAMO | Dan D'Eramo, zfc::deramo | Mon Jul 20 1992 22:57 | 5 |
| A bounded function f:[a,b] -> R is Riemann integrable if
and only if it is continuous almost everywhere, i.e.,
except for a set of Lebesgue measure zero.
Dan
|