[Search for users] [Overall Top Noters] [List of all Conferences] [Download this site]

Conference rusure::math

Title:Mathematics at DEC
Moderator:RUSURE::EDP
Created:Mon Feb 03 1986
Last Modified:Fri Jun 06 1997
Last Successful Update:Fri Jun 06 1997
Number of topics:2083
Total number of notes:14613

768.0. ""unwell-ordering" " by SCRIBE::PORTNOY () Mon Oct 12 1987 14:05

In trying to prove the well-ordering principle by induction (i.e., every set of
positive integers has a least member), I stumbled into what one might
call the "unwell-ordering" principle (i.e., every set of positive integers
has a greatest member).

Obviously the induction is spurious, but I haven't the slightest idea
what's wrong with it. The induction is layed out below, with the hope
that someone can point out where I goofed.

Each one-element sequence of positive integers has a greatest
element. Assume that each sequence of k positive integers has a greatest
element, call it g. Then each sequence of k+1 positive integers has a
greatest element, i.e., max (g, k+1). Thus, each sequence of positive
integers has a greatest element.

Alvin
T.RTitleUserPersonal
Name
DateLines
768.1CIMNET::KOLKERConan the LibrarianMon Oct 12 1987 14:318
    re .0
    
    You have successfully proven that every finite subset of the integers
    has a greatest element.  
    
    What you have *not* proven [and you can't since it is false] is
    that an arbitrary subset of the integers has a largest element
    
768.2does everyone know the proof?VINO::JMUNZERMon Oct 12 1987 17:123
    But the coins on the table are all heads or all tails.
    
    John
768.3CIMNET::KOLKERConan the LibrarianMon Oct 12 1987 18:4523
    re .2
    
    I think this old saw is used as cautionary tale in applying
    mathematical induction carelessly. Let me have a go at it.
    
    Suppose a set of coins has only one member. Then the coins in the
    set are all heads or all tails. That is case = 1
    
    Assume it is true for case = n.
    
    Add a new coin to the set. This new coin and an n-1 subset of the
    original constitute an n set. Assume wlog they are all heads. The
    original n set must have been all heads therefore the n+1 set is
    all heads.  There fore for all n, the coins are all heads.
    
    Where did this "induction" break down?
    
    Answer below
    
    For n = 2 we cannot assert the new (second coin) has the same side
    showing as a proper subset of the remaining coins, for that would
    be an empty set.
    
768.4But this time, it's true!ZFC::DERAMODaniel V. D'EramoMon Oct 12 1987 19:102
    But induction can be used to prove that all positive integers are
    interesting.  Who remembers that one?
768.5Zorn's Lemma, Axiom of Choice, W O princ., Induct.TLE::BRETTTue Oct 13 1987 10:0326
    Since the use of induction depends on the well-ordering principle,
    it can't be proved by it!
                   
    Summary of induction...
    
    Given a proposition, P(x : POSITIVE) -> BOOLEAN,  show that P is
    true for all x.
    
    The F be the nonempty set of positive integers for which P(x) -> FALSE.
    F has some least member (well ordering principle!), say n.
    
    If n = 1, then prove P(1)  {first step of an inductive proof}.
    
    If n > 1, then prove P(x-1) => P(x) and, since x-1 is not in F
    conclude that x is not also {inductive step}.
    
    Hence conclude that F must be empty.
    
    
    However, notice that IF the well ordering principle is NOT true,
    then there could be sets of positive integers without a least element
    and hence it is impossible to select "n" above, and hence induction
    doesn't work.
    
   /Bevin 
768.6CIMNET::KOLKERConan the LibrarianTue Oct 13 1987 11:199
    reply to all integers are interesting
    
    proof after line feed:
    Suppose there exist uninteresting integers. Then by well ordering
    there must be a smallest uninteresting integer. But that is kind
    of interesting, I mean really, the whole idea that all the
    un-interesting integers have to be larger. Right?  The contradiction
    carries the day.
    
768.7Since you can well-order ANY set,SQM::HALLYBI sell too soonTue Oct 13 1987 12:042
    The same "proof" applies to real and complex numbers, 
    as well as function spaces and yet larger sets...
768.8BEING::POSTPISCHILAlways mount a scratch monkey.Tue Oct 13 1987 17:027
    Re .7:
    
    Not all sets have a smallest member, such as the set of all real
    numbers greater than one.
    
    
    				-- edp 
768.9ZFC::DERAMODaniel V. D'EramoTue Oct 13 1987 18:2837
.5>>    However, notice that IF the well ordering principle is NOT true,
.5>>    then there could be sets of positive integers without a least element
.5>>    and hence it is impossible to select "n" above, and hence induction
.5>>    doesn't work.

     No -- Zorn's lemma, the axiom of choice, the well ordering
     principle, apply to arbitrary sets.  The well ordering
     principle could be false -- for example, there may be no
     well ordering of all real numbers -- but even so the set of
     positive integers is still well ordered by its "natural"
     ordering.  The "highly structured" set of positive integers
     can be well ordered without having to appeal to Zorn's lemma
     or the axiom of choice.

     Re .6:  That's the proof!

.7>>    Since you can well-order ANY set,
.7>>    The same "proof" applies to real and complex numbers, 
.7>>    as well as function spaces and yet larger sets...

     Not really.  The standard or natural ordering of the
     positive integers is a well ordering, and under this
     ordering there is no "least" uninteresting positive integer.
     But as stated in .7, the reals are not well-ordered under
     their natural ordering, and it's not as interesting when
     they are well ordered by some hypothetical ordering whose
     existence is established by the axiom of choice.

.8>>    Re .7:
.8>>    
.8>>    Not all sets have a smallest member, such as the set of all real
.8>>    numbers greater than one.

     Right.  It is the standard ordering of the reals that
     matters, and that is not a well ordering of the reals.

     Dan
768.10TLE::BRETTWed Oct 14 1987 11:034
    I'm intrigued, can you prove that the set of positive integers is
    well-ordered by the normal "<" operator without the use of induction?
                                                              
    /Bevin
768.11CLT::GILBERTBuilderWed Oct 14 1987 14:107
>   I'm intrigued, can you prove that the set of positive integers is
>   well-ordered by the normal "<" operator without the use of induction?

    It's best to just assume the set of positive integers; it is a 'given'
    in this problem, and so we shouldn't need to prove (inductively) that
    it exists.  What's the definition of the normal "<" operator?  And do
    you have a non-inductive definition of "well-ordered"?
768.12Do you believe in positive integers?ZFC::DERAMODaniel V. D&#039;EramoWed Oct 14 1987 22:1820
.10>>    I'm intrigued, can you prove that the set of positive integers is
.10>>    well-ordered by the normal "<" operator without the use of induction?

     If first order logic is what you prove things in, then the
     usual axioms of number theory include an axiom scheme for
     induction.  So in that sense induction is assumed as a
     property of the positive integers.  The usual axioms of set
     theory are strong enough to define a set [call it Fred] and
     operations on that set that make Fred look exactly like what
     everyone thinks positive integers are.  One can prove
     [without the axiom of choice] that the set Fred is well
     ordered by the operation Fred-< that looks exactly like the
     < of the positive integers.  So in that sense, one can prove
     that the positive integers are well-ordered by <, and the
     proof does not use or assume induction over positive integers.

     So in number theory, induction is an assumed property of the
     positive integers; in set theory, it can be proven that
     these things called positive integers have the property that
     things can be proven about them using induction.
768.13some 'usual' definitions:CHOVAX::YOUNGBack from the Shadows Again,Wed Oct 14 1987 22:4744
    The 'usual' definition of the Natural Numbers (ie. the positive
    integers) is that they are the set (or they are isomorphic to any
    set that) conforms to Peanos Postulates:
    
    	For a set N: (informally stated)
    
    	P1:  1 is in N
    	P2:  If (x) is in N then successor(x) is also in N
    	P3:  If (x) and (y) are in N and ( succ.(x) = succ.(y) ) 
    		then ( x = y )
    	P4:  There is no (x) in N such that ( succ.(x) = 1 )
    	P5:  If 1 is in a set P and if the successor of every element
    		in P is also in P then P is equivilent to N. 
    		( Induction )
    
    The 'usual' definition for the '<' (less than) operator is that
    it is a relation over the Natural numbers such that:
    	
    	If ( a < b ) then
    	either
    		successor(a) = b
    	or
    		successor(a) < b
    
    The 'usual' definition of the Well-Ordering principle is:
    	
    	A Set T is Well-Ordered with respect to a relation L 
    	IFF   For any subset S of T 
    		Either
        		S is the empty set
    		Or
    			there exists some (x) in S such that for any
    			other (y) in S ==> x.L.y
    			( which is to say that S has a least member )

    
    I might also add that one of my number theory texts (Shockley) has
    a proof that the Induction Postulate (P5) is equivalent to the
    Well-Ordering Principle for < over Natural numbers.
    
    I won't post the proof in case anyone wishes to work it out for
    themselves.
    
    --  Barry
768.14first & second order logics...CHOVAX::YOUNGBack from the Shadows Again,Wed Oct 14 1987 22:5916
    Re .12:
    
    Actually the Induction Postulate is usualy stated in Second-Order
    terms, ie.:
        
    	For any set T then T is equivilent to N IFF ...
    
    When your phrasing things in terms of sets as variables, then you
    are talking in at least second order logic.
    
    (  well actually with a lot of fancy footwork and extra postulates
     you can state any second order postulate in first order terms,
     but in practice no one ever bothers ).

    
    --  Barry
768.15FOUL! You can't have it both ways, guysSQM::HALLYBI sell too soonThu Oct 15 1987 13:0323
.7>    The same "proof" applies to real and complex numbers, 
.7>    as well as function spaces and yet larger sets...

.8>    Re .7:
.8>    Not all sets have a smallest member, such as the set of all real
.8>    numbers greater than one.
    
    Not true.  Let E be "the set of all real numbers greater than one".
    Use the Well Ordering Theorem to well order E.  Under this
    well-ordering, certainly not the normal "<" ordering, every
    subset of E has a least member.  That's an interesting number, etc.
    
    DVD's response to this line of reasoning is:

.9>      Right.  It is the standard ordering of the reals that
.9>      matters, and that is not a well ordering of the reals.

    Which, while entirely correct, is a matter of his opinion.  In fact,
    the definition of "interesting" is a matter of opinion, and is the
    downfall of this entire line of reasoning even for finite sets of
    Mersenne Primes.
    
      John 
768.16TLE::BRETTThu Oct 15 1987 15:0613
    Actually, given that the well-ordering theorem can provide SOME
    "<" function that well-order's the positive reals, we can easily
    construct MANY "<" functions that do (by composing the W-O "<" with
    any 1-1, onto function from the positive reals to the positive reals)
    and hence we can chose some "<" that makes ANY particular element
    of the set of "uninteresting" reals the least member, and hence
    (since this is NOT a 'privileged' position in the set) it is BORING
    that for some artificially constructed "<", a particular number
    is the least in the "uninteresting reals" set.  I believe this
    breaks the proof for reals.  The point about the integer proof is
    that the "<" is NOT an artificially created one.
    
    /Bevin
768.17That's an interesting argumentSQM::HALLYBI sell too soonThu Oct 15 1987 16:409
>    The point about the integer proof is that the "<" is NOT an 
>    artificially created one.

    Of course it's artificial.  You're just a lot more familiar with it.

    Proof by massive harumph-ing is no more valid than any of the various
    techniques used by the Spanish Inquisition to coerce the heathens.
    
      John
768.18Were the integers discovered or invented?ZFC::DERAMODaniel V. D&#039;EramoThu Oct 15 1987 20:0520
.17>>   >    The point about the integer proof is that the "<" is NOT an 
.17>>   >    artificially created one.
.17>>
.17>>   Of course it's artificial.  You're just a lot more familiar with it.

     Aha!  A religious comment!  "A famous person" (sorry, I
     can't remember the source) said something like:

          God created the integers, all the rest is man's invention.

     A non-mathematician once told me that he "believed" in the
     existence of the integers.  Many more people feel the
     integers exist, somewhere out there, than feel that
     function spaces (for example) exist.  So statements about
     whether or not < is artificial are starting to get personal.

     Dan

     P.S.  The development from .4 to here has been ...
           interesting! :-)